Date: Thu, 21 Aug 1997 11:14:15 -0400 (EDT) To: bhaskar-AT-jefferson.village.virginia.edu Subject: Re: BHA: Bhaskar, dialectics and immanent criticism In "Dialectic" RB offers us a series of different and in some respects complementary types of critique that DCR thought can engage in. Immanent critique he defines in terms of the revelation from within of theory/practice inconsistencies within ruling ideologies, in contrast to, say, what he terms "ommisive" and "achilles heel" modes of critique. Within the field of political & constitutional and legal theory there does appear to be considerable scope for contrasting discrepancies between what liberal democratic ideologies of freedom, justice and equal treatment promise as universal entitlements of citizenship, and what an antagonistic society actually "delivers up" at the level of the empirical lived experience of those it victimises. My own question is what are the limits of, and difficulties for, the dialectical strategy of immanent criticism, even within this apparently fruitful sphere of application? Whilst a number of counter-arguments have occurred to me whilst typing up these points, (not surprising since I have long been an advocate and would-be practitioner of IC), I wonder what others on this list think of the following possible objects to this mode of critique. 1/. It is arguable that immanent critique requires a contradictory mixture of motivations and presuppositions. Critics must initially presuppose the existence of a contingent discrepancy between legal rhetoric and reality otherwise there would be no point in even considering carrying out immanent criticism. However, internal critics only pretend, in a deceitful fashion, to accept various legal ideals, whilst this cynical pretence is itself grounded in a utopian gesture of hope. Yet scepticism concerning an identity between ideological rhetoric of law and its actuality can often be heightened during the process of immanent critique, something which inevitably subverts any element of hope. 2/. It can also be objected that some absolute form of external 'foundationalism' is an absolute pre-requisite for any social scientific critique of law without which all evaluation is condemned to the well-known self-contradictions of moral relativism. And whenever the norms for evaluation are taken from the target of critique, researchers disable themselves from being able to criticise those totalitarian and racist regimes which are most deserving of critique. Here we can ask: "Is it a sufficient basis for criticising a totalitarian regime to simply exploit how its practices fall short of its own anti-democratic ideals by still retaining various semblance of constitutionality? Here the implication is that immanent criticism is valid, if at all, only when applied to regimes whose constitutional ideals are, in some sense, 'progressive'. This foundationalist objection clearly objects to the reflexive claim of dialectical theory that it forms part, and is implicated within, the historical changes which it seeks to comprehend, and there is ever reason to doubt whether its criteria, research methods, concepts and findings will achieve an absolute degree of finality which remains true for all time. 3/. The immanent critique of legal ideologies clearly presupposes an initial value-judgement in favour of concrete freedom over internally unjustifiable constraints. Such critique assumes that priority should be given to self-conscious forms of social self-determination over the ideological domination of merely traditional, customary or institutional imperatives that are themselves lacking any form of democratic accountability. The underlying democratic interest which informs immanent critique is that of enhancing the capacities of the 'human subject' to exercise rational autonomy within the context of a unified community. It is doubtful whether the initial preference for freedom from determination by irrational social and ideological forces can itself be 'validated' independently of the results of critique itself. Hence, immanent critique must simply presuppose the validity of enlightenment forms of rationalism expressed through knowledge about law which can - in principle - help liberate us from unwarranted relations of power, mythology and authority.Yet to those postmodern scholars, who pronounce the "death" of the subject of legal and human rights as part of the demise of the entire enlightenment project will find little reason to accept this pre-supposition. 4/. A related 'modernist' assumption made by dialectical analysis is that cultural traditions are still open to a reflexive type of self-understanding that is sufficient to allow us to develop a genuinely critical standpoint upon them. Immanent criticism of law presupposes that its target is reflexive in the sense of possessing a discernable self-interpretation of the normative value of its own practices. If this presupposition turns out to be invalid, then it is not only pointless to expose discrepancies between the rhetoric and reality of law but also naive to expect this 'disclosure' to lead to any practical difference in institutional practices. Another related assumption is any exposed discrepancies will be perceived as a problem by the institutions themselves sufficient at least to alter their institutional practices. Lichterman notes: "In a sense, academic practitioners of immanent critique and its variants also accept the premise that law's putative ideal of formal, rational discourse pervades society, if only by implicitly asserting that mere exposure of contradiction or incoherence can bring about social change." (1994: 1053-54). Michael Salter --- from list bhaskar-AT-lists.village.virginia.edu ---
Display software: ArchTracker © Malgosia Askanas, 2000-2005