Date: Mon, 12 Jul 1999 15:15:05 +1000 Subject: BHA: Begin the Dialectic Fellow Listtees, I will post tomorrow the first of two posts on Diffracting the dialectic, but I thought I would warm us up with this post on the dialectic from the paper I gave at Essex. Some of it has appeared on the list before, I think, but it will do no harm I hope to put it all in here. regards Gary Of the dialectic and the development of Dialectical Critical Realism Few concepts in philosophy have engendered as much controversy, misunderstanding and, it must be said, opprobrium as that of the dialectic. Indeed Bhaskar himself describes the dialectic as the 'most complex - and hotly contested - concept' (Bhaskar, 1993: 15). One of the most influential sources of an anti-dialectical attitude has been the work of Karl Popper. Throughout a long career he repeatedly attacked the dialectic and Hegelian thought in general. Something of Popper's loathing (sic) of both Hegel and his dialectical method can be gauged from this quotation: Hebel's fame was made by those who prefer a quick initiation into the deeper secrets of this world to the laborious technicalities of a science, which, after all, may only disappoint them by its lack of power to unveil all mysteries. For they soon found out that nothing could be applied with such ease to any problem whatsoever, and at the same time with such impressive (though only apparent) difficulty, and with such quick and sure but imposing success, nothing could be used as cheaply and with so little scientific training and knowledge, and nothing would give such a spectacular scientific air, as did Hegelian dialectics, the mystery method that replaced 'barren formal logic' (Popper, 1974: 27-8). I shall return to the specific relations between the Hegelian and the Bhaskarian dialectics. In so doing I shall attempt to form a judgement as to what extent the strictures against Hegel's dialectic are a) justifiable and more importantly b) applicable to the dialectic of DCR, but first some history. Bhaskar has pointed out that the dialectic did not begin with Hegel. Indeed its origins lie in the Eleatic and Ionian traditions of Greek Philosophy. The Eleatic strand provided the impetus for the dialectic as the art of conversation, discussion and reasoning. The foremost exemplar of this mode of dialectic was to become Socrates. Dialectic in this case meant above all a means of reaching truth through reason. However within the Ionian tradition, dialectic meant process. This process typically meant the establishment of a higher reality, usually God or the Forms, and then the manifestation of this higher reality at a lower level in the world. Hegel combined the Eleatic and Ionian strands to produce a dialectic which began with Reason - the Absolute, which is then alienated and becomes something other than itself, only to have its original unity restored when it recognises that the alienation is only the manifestation of itself (Bhaskar, 1993: 17-18). Marx took over the dialectic from Hegel and attempted to rescue it from Idealism by substituting matter for Reason and the Absolute. However the Marxian dialectic still retained a preference for a dialectical process which was both built around internal contradictions and proceeded in an autogenetic and linear manner. Michael Forster in his defence of the Hegelian dialectic lists three standard criticisms of Hegel's method (Forster, 1993: 130-70). Firstly there is the charge from Popper that Hegel 'affirms contradictions'. The second accusation against the Hegelian dialectic is that it proceeds in a linear and automatic fashion. The third objection is that the dialectic is necessarily constructed around the alleged self-contradictoriness of our fundamental categories. I do not have the space to deal in detail with Forster's defence of Hegel except to note that it is weakened by his acceptance of the fundamental premise of the attack, namely that being or reality is logical (Forster, 1993: 142). The underlying error in this case is the definition of being in terms of thought or logic. Bhaskar advances a transcendental argument here that things would not change unless there were contradictory forces and processes at work. But we do in fact know that change exists (Bhaskar, 1993: 75), therefore being is not reducible to logic. Whatever the merit, however, of the objections, that Forster has listed, to the Hegelian (and Marxist) dialectic they do not apply in Bhaskar's case. The Bhaskarian dialectic differs from its Hegelian predecessor in several very important ways. To begin with Bhaskar's dialectic is four-termed unlike Hegel's triad. Thus where Hegel has identity, negativity and totality, Bhaskar has non-identity, negativity, totality and transformative agency. Moreover negativity and totality are given radically different interpretations to Hegel within the DCR model (Bhaskar, 1993: xiii). The first term of Bhaskar's dialectic, non-identity, implies a strong rejection of Hegel's identification of subject and object in thought. Bhaskar incorporates into his concept of non-identity most of the crucial concepts which have informed from the beginning the whole Critical Realist project. Thus we have the notions of a structured, stratified and differentiated reality, the separation of epistemology and ontology within ontology, the transitive and intransitive dimensions, emergence, change and openness. This first element in the dialectic constitutes the first moment (1M) in the new model of Dialectical Critical Realism (Bhaskar, 1993: 8). The second term of Bhaskar's dialectic, negativity, is the narrowly dialectic moment. It has to be understood in terms of Bhaskar's expansion of ontology to include non-existence or absence. Here Bhaskar rejects the whole tradition of Western philosophy, which he traces back to Parmenides, of seeing reality in purely positive terms. Bhaskar labels this as the error of 'ontological monovalence' and argues that the chief result of this tradition has been to =85 erase the contingency of existential questions and to despatialize and detemporalise (accounts of) being (1993: 7). The metaphor which Bhaskar employs to underscore the contrast between his ontology and the positive ontology of the Parmenidean tradition is that of the =85 positive as a tiny, but important ripple on the surface of a sea of negativity (1993: 5). The second term of the Bhaskarian dialectic, negativity, forms what Bhaskar terms the second edge (2E) of his model. It is worth pointing out here the radical potential in the rejection of ontological monovalence. Parmenides denied the reality of time, plurality and motion, that is his philosophy served to naturalise and thus support Das Bestehende - the existing state of affairs. Interestingly Ernst Bloch developed a somewhat parallel concept to ontological monovalence, which he called 'been-ness'. This referred primarily to Plato's description of knowledge as anamnesis or remembering of something seen before. In other words Plato, under the influence of Parmenides, rejected novelty and change, or, as Bloch put it, the Not-Yet-Being (Bloch, 1986: 141). I shall be dealing later with some of the differences between the Hegelian and Bhaskarian dialectical moments, when I come to discuss the diffraction of the dialectic. But here I will note that in DCR there is no automatic process of aufhebung or sublation from one term to another. Bhaskar's dialectic accounts for dialectical connection as well as contradiction, the latter being seen as a special case of the former. Most importantly for Bhaskar only a sub-class of dialectical contradictions involve logical contradictions and these may be described and potentially explained without contradiction. Nor do the processes involved in the dialectical moment automatically lead to progression to a higher level as they do in the Hegelian system. Within the DCR dialectic, development can also mean relations of regression, retrogression and decay. The third term of Bhaskar's dialectic, totality, marks another important departure from the Hegelian and indeed some instances of the Marxist versions of this notion. Within the Hegelian totality we have the phenomenon of closure which gives us theses such as Fukuyama's the 'end of history'. Bhaskar's totality by contrast is radically open and perhaps to emphasise this point he talks most often of totalities. So the Bhaskarian dialectic does not provide us with an automatic passage to the end of history be that interpreted as the Absolute as in Hegel or as Communism in Marx's Manifesto. This third term of the Bhaskarian dialectic forms the third level (3L) of the DCR model. Given the troubled history of the concept of totality it is important to emphasise that the Bhaskarian totality is not an expression of a single element as in the expressivist totality of vulgar Marxism, for example Nikolai Bukharin. With the latter the superstructure is seen as the straightforward expression of the economic base (Bukharin, 1925). This very openness of the Bhaskarian totality necessitates a fourth element in his dialectic, namely that of agency. It is agency, which if allied to projects that are grounded in rationality, may produce the eudemonistic or good society where humanity as a species can flourish (Bhaskar, 1993: 9). This element of the dialectic, agency, is characterised as the fourth dimension (4D) within the DCR model. To sum up this section, the DCR dialectic is four termed rather than triadic as in Hegel's system. The Bhaskarian dialectic is like the Marxian dialectic in that it is grounded in ontology rather than in ideas as with Hegel. However Bhaskar gives us a unique account of ontology in that it is built round the notion of absence. Moreover the Bhaskarian dialectic differs from its Hegelian and some of its Marxist predecessors in that it provides no guarantees. Whether we reach the eudemonistic society or not depends on us rather than on some autogenetic linear process. Diffracting the Dialectic The diffraction of the dialectic is dealt with in considerable detail in Bhaskar (1993). However an interestingly earlier step towards this process is taken in Reclaiming Reality where he discusses the possibilities raised by Marx's critique of Hegel' philosophy of identity. Here Bhaskar argues that: One possibility raised by Marx's critique of Hegel's philosophy of identity is that the dialectic in Marx (and Marxism) may not specify a unitary phenomenon, but a number of different figures and topics. Thus it may refer to patterns or process in philosophy, science or the world; being, thought or their relation (ontological, epistemological and relational dialectics); nature or society, 'in' or 'out of' time (historical or structural dialectics); which are universal or particular, trans-historical or transient and so on (Bhaskar, 1989: 119, original emphasis). Taking our cue from this we can say that the Critical Realist dialectic cannot be contained within a simple triadic formula of the thesis - antithesis - synthesis kind. We should note here that Hegel never used this formulation to describe his dialectic. Nor does Bhaskar employ this terminology. Bhaskar takes his starting point for the diffraction of the dialectic from Marx's materialist critique of the idealism of the Hegelian dialectic (Bhaskar, 1993:86-96). By contrast with the unity of the Hegelian Absolute, Marx's critique emphasises that the world is differentiated. As a consequence the dialectic if it is to accord with the 'complexities, angularities, nuances of our pluriversal world' must itself be diffracted. Diffraction allows us, Bhaskar argues, to call upon a host of 'topologies, choreographies and genealogies' (Bhaskar, 1993: 96). Bhaskar gives two kinds of definition of dialectic. The first is tied closely to his extension of the notion of ontology or reality to include absence. Here dialectic is the process of =85the absenting of absence, and in the human realm as the specifically efficacious agentive...absenting of absence (1993: 173). Bhaskar also expands the intension of the dialectic to mean =85merely any sort of relationship between differential elements, which can obviously be put through a variety of hoops (1993: 174). Following then this process of diffraction one can approach a text and identify and analyse the variety of dialectics at work. However there is a crucial moment in this analysis. The dialectic having been diffracted must also be retotalised. For Bhaskar it is the dialectics of absence that will perform this role (1993: 98). What then are the 'dialectics of absence'? This is the process by which conflictual interaction becomes change that can be regarded as absenting. The dialectic generally involves the absenting of absences. Most crucially those constraints which are preventing the absenting of ills are themselves absented. This leads to a general human flourishing and the development of human flourishing in nature (Bhaskar, 1993: 177). There have of course been objections to this widening of the dialectic. Thus John Mingers commented: His generalisation of 'dialectic' beyond the Hegelian...seems to me to make it so general that it includes almost any form or dynamic relationship between entities, events, or process (Mingers, 10.6.97). Mingers went on to ask: Does he (Bhaskar) mean it this widely? If so haven't we lost a useful term? (ibid) The answers to these questions are - yes and no. The 'yes' is qualified, though, by the definition of dialectical connection as being =85between entities or aspects of a totality such that they are in principle distinct but inseparable (Bhaskar, 1993: 58). References Bhaskar, R., _Reclaiming Reality_, London: Verso, 1989 __________, _Dialectic: The pulse of Freedom_, London: Verso, 1993 Bloch, E., _The Principle of Hope_, Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1986 Bukharin, N., Historical Materialism: A System of Sociology, New York: International Publishers, 1925 Forster, _Hegel's Dialectical Method_ in Beiser, F.C. (ed) _The Cambridge Companion to Hegel_, New York: Cambridge University Press, 1993: 130-70 Mingers, J., _Bhaskar List Posting_, 10. 6. 1997 Popper, K., The Open Society and its Enemies, Volume 2, Hegel and Marx_, London: Routlege, 1974 --- from list bhaskar-AT-lists.village.virginia.edu ---
Display software: ArchTracker © Malgosia Askanas, 2000-2005