Date: Sat, 5 Jul 2003 20:49:15 +0100 Subject: BHA: [fyi] Interview with Manuel De Landa - part 3 III. "I think Marxism is Deleuze and Guattari's little Oedipus, the small piece of territory they must keep to come back to at night after a wild day of deterritorializing." (Manuel De Landa, CTHEORY Interview) CTHEORY (Selinger): My question here concerns your sense of the value of phenomenological analysis. Deleuze was a staunch critic of phenomenology. He saw it as a subjective style of philosophy that reduced the plane of immanence to that which appears for consciousness. However, I recently found a reference that struck me as interesting in light of your work. In order to explain to those who are not familiar with self-organizing processes how essences are created, you point to how it is not possible to explain the coming into being of the spherical form of a soap bubble with appealing to "endogenously-generated stable states." In other words, without appealing to the science of self-organization, it is impossible to explain how the essence of "soap-bubbleness" is not constituted by way of an ideal geometric form imposing itself upon an inert collection of molecules from the outside (i.e. hylomorphic schema). Let me use this example to initiate a dialogue with phenomenology. In Maurice Merleau-Ponty's early work, The Structure of Behavior, he tries to explain how an organism's preferred mode of behavior is constituted, such that what is experienced as "the simplest" and "most natural" is that mode of behavior that gives the organism a feeling of balance and facility. Merleau-Ponty writes: Is the orientation toward these preferred modes of behavior comparable to the formation of a spherical soap bubble? In the latter case, the external forces exerted on the surface of the soap bubble tend to compress it into a point; the pressure of the enclosed air on the other hand demands as large a volume as possible. The spherical solution which is realized represents the only possible solution to this problem of minimum and maximum. Can it be said in the same way that the preferred modes of behavior of an organism are those which, in the de facto conditions in which it finds itself, objectively offer the greatest simplicity and the greatest unity? In his article, "The Current Relevance of Merleau-Ponty's Phenomenology of Embodiment," Hubert Dreyfus claims that Merleau-Ponty responds to this latter query in the affirmative: The bubble starts as a deformed film. The bits of soap just respond to the local forces according to laws which happen to work so as to dispose the entire system to end up as a sphere, but the spherical result does not play any causal role in producing the bubble. The same holds for the final gestalt of body and racket in my example. Indeed, I cannot represent how I should turn my racket since I do not know what I do when I return the ball. I may once have been told to hold my racket perpendicular to the court, and I may have succeeded in doing so, but now experience has sculpted my swing to the situation in a far more subtle and appropriate way than I could have achieved as a beginner following this rule. What do you think of the phenomenological appeal to the self-organized process of a soap-bubble in order to explain the relation between perception and skill acquisition? Do you think that this example suggests there may be a richer relationship between phenomenology and Deleuzeian ontology? De Landa: There have been many people who have tried to come up with some kind of "soap bubble" explanation for aspects of human behavior: the bubble minimizes surface tension, so we "minimize effort" or something like that. This is fine with me as long as it is clear this is just a hypothesis that needs testing. But to assume that there is some "law" that everything in the world must be governed by a "least principle" is wrong. (It assumes the only virtual multiplicities are those characterized by a single steady-state singularity). It very well may be that aspects of the stability of perceptual fields do in fact depend on least principles (or steady-state stability: the famous Necker Cube or the duck-rabbit illusion of Wittgenstein surely indicate our vision can jump from one to another stable state). But now, is there a way of discovering these stable states from within (phenomenologically)? Or do we have to use psychophysics and other disciplines (neural networks, for example, which do use steady states) in order to approach the question? And, at any rate, why only steady states, why not periodic or other singularities? And why a unique one (as in the soap bubble) as opposed to a multiplicity with broken-symmetry levels (to account for the fact that our experience changes if we ingest alcohol, or psychedelics)? CTHEORY (Ihde): I agree. I have long been critical of Merleau-Ponty's interpretation of Necker Cubes vis-a-vis my notion of multistability. Like a number of psychologists, Merleau-Ponty mistakenly thinks that the reversibility of the cube is what is unique about the cube. In my version of phenomenology, the structures of perception are best discovered through variational method; this allows one to investigate the whole range of possibilities from those of ordinary sediments to the most extreme horizontal possibilities. CTHEORY (Jensen): A different but related question arises from the fact that even though you take your analysis to be realist, this does not delimit the interpretive flexibility of readers -- that is, their abilities to take your accounts as supporting their specific projects regardless of whether you would approve of that use or not. For instance, in a recent talk at Duke, Zizek invoked your understanding of Deleuze as the only correct one. Nevertheless, my feeling is that his psychoanalytically informed way of evaluating the correctness and plausibility of Deleuzian interpretations, including yours, is something you would vehemently oppose. As you espouse the idea of a "correct understanding," how do you think about and/or handle readers who misunderstand or otherwise misuse your work? De Landa: Well, it would all have to be handled case by case. As long as Freud can be taken to have given us a process of individuation (via the Oedipal drama) his ideas fit the ontology I propose. A philosopher can only specify that a historical individuation process must be given but not what exactly those processes are (which is a question for the specialists). The part of Freud where he gives an account of personal individuation may be right or wrong in reality, but it is compatible with my ontology. The part where he attempts to define society as a kind of projection from these mental structures violates the ontology: institutional organizations and norms are individuated following another real historical process and are not just mental projections. So that part has to be rejected. A similar treatment would have to be given for each concrete individual entity. Now, to the extent that many proposed processes are compatible with the basic ontology (while they may be incompatible with one another) there can be many interpretations of it. Yet this does not mean any reading will be compatible: I still wonder how a phenomenologist would find my ideas compatible or even useful. CTHEORY (Protevi): Intensive Science and Virtual Philosophy accepts Deleuze's use of axiomatics to analyze major or Royal science. Yet you are critical of Deleuze and Guattari's use of axiomatics as a way to conceptualize capitalism (e.g., ATY 331n7), which you see as an example of a top-down positing of a whole. I certainly would agree with you that far too much Marxist work has been simplistic, historical determinist, reductive, totalizing, functionalist, top-down, etc., but I wonder if you aren't being too harsh with Deleuze and Guattari's attempts to define a theory of capitalism that avoids each of these dangers? They certainly adopt a notion of "machinic surplus value," moving beyond a simple labor theory of value (machines as "congealed muscular energy," as you put it at ATY 79). Don't they also consistently deny any historical determinism of stages of development by emphasizing the contingency of capitalist formations, as well as conduct a sustained polemic against reductive base-superstructure models of society? Don't their constant reminders that the line of flight is primary prevent any totalizing accounts? Isn't their use of axiomatics an attempt to see capitalism as an adaptive meshwork of economic, state and quasi-state (IMF, WTO, etc.) institutions, rather than as a homeostatic organismic whole, as in crude functionalist accounts? In other words, haven't they, at least in principle, given us the outlines of a bottom-up account of a complex, open-ended, adaptive world capitalist system? De Landa: I agree that if I had to choose among all the Marxist accounts of economic history I would probably pick theirs. It does have all the advantages you mention. Yet, I believe they would have benefited greatly from a better reading of Braudel. They seemed to have read only volume one of his history of capitalism and not the other two volumes, which are really the most radical part. This is clear when in A Thousand Plateus in one page thet quote Braudel's stress on the role of cities and yet in the very next page Deleuze and Guattari go on to define capitalism as a "market economy", an idea which Braudel attacks as historically false. So I wonder what would have happened to their theory had they understood the last point: that there is no such thing as "the market" in general and no such thing as a "logic of exchange" in general (doesn't the idea of an capitalist axiomatic depend on the idea of a logic of exchange?). Once we separate oligopolies from the market (they are strategic not primarily exchangist entities) and identify capitalism with oligopolies (as Braudel does) we can still use some of Deleuze and Guattari's ideas since markets have always caused "lines of flight" to pass among societies, particularly closed societies (it's in the marketplace that we meet outsiders; that foreign objects and ideas enter a city; that heterogeneity is injected etc). CTHEORY (Protevi): Yes, you're completely right that Deleuze and Guattari overlook Braudel's distinction between market and anti-market and use an abstract sense of capitalism as a "market economy" whereby "market" means "any exchange system whatsoever, whether it is composed of atomic producers and consumers who must act as price-takers (the Braudelian sense of 'local market') or whether it is composed of producers and consumers with varying degrees of power to be price-setters (the Braudelian sense of 'anti-markets')." Even though it's sometimes hard to make that distinction clearly all the time (for instance, when you say in your answer "it's in the marketplace that we meet outsiders; that foreign objects and ideas enter a city" I think Braudel would attribute this to long-distance trade dominated by anti-market corporations, even if it occurs in the same physical location as local market exchanges), I agree we should by all means incorporate that distinction into our analysis of the economies (note the plural) operating today worldwide. Here the neo-Marxist notions of formal and real subsumption (roughly speaking, the relations between capitalist and non-capitalist economies, and the tendency of the former to replace the latter) would have to be brought to bear, notions that Hardt and Negri use often in Empire. (Just to be clear before I continue: I completely agree with you in everything you say about Marx himself in the 19th century being wed to equilibrium analyses, about the complete bankruptcy of top-down and centralized social and economic planning, about the necessity of using non-linear analyses of economic processes that show the inadequacy of equilibrium and optimizing models, and so forth.) Here is my question to you: I wonder if Deleuze and Guattari ignore the Braudelian distinction because, like Marx, they locate the important element to be examined in capitalism to be production rather than exchange? Recapitulating what they say in both Anti-Oedipus and A Thousand Plateaus, what they call in What is Philosophy? "Marx's concept of capitalism" (97) is the conjunction of the deterritorialized flows of labor and capital, and these meet in production, not in exchange. De Landa: Well, no, not really. I agree that the dichotomy "market/antimarket" does give that impression, hence I probably won't use it again. But the same distinction applies to production: it's the difference between economies of scale and economies of agglomeration. That is, between oligopolies using managed prices, routinized labor, hierarchical structure, vertical integration etc. and networks of small producers using market prices, skilled labor, decentralized structure and functional complementarities. You must remember the study that compares Silicon Valley and Route 128 as production systems (mentioned in A Thousand Years of Nonlinear History) or what I have written about Emilia-Romagna. Braudel (and Jane Jacobs following in his steps) places a great emphasis on this distinction (though he does not use the terms) and views it as applying across history for at least a millennium (hence economies of agglomeration would not be a late stage of capitalism as some Marxists have tried to argue using the term "flexible specialization" or the ridiculous one of "post-Fordism") but an alternative to economies of scale (also much older than the Industrial Revolution) which has been there for a while. CTHEORY (Protevi): What about the emphasis on production as the key ontological concept in Anti-Oedipus (the whole world, nature and humans together, is composed of interlocking series of connected machines that produce materials that are fed into other machines)? De Landa: This is correct. I myself add to this when I attack the Humean notion of causality (as perceived constant conjunction) and define it as a real connection in which one event produces another event. And more generally, when I stress that to get rid of essences one must always give the intensive process of production that yields any individual entity (atoms, organisms or commodities). Intensive thinking in general is about production. CTHEORY (Protevi): From this productivist perspective (which I think is amenable to a nonlinear dynamics analysis of the material and energy flows that keep the open production systems far-from-equilibrium), the key issue is the productive conjunction of capital and labor (here machinic surplus value vitiates a pure labor theory of value), whether or not the products of that labor flow into markets or anti-markets. And the key to coercing labor into exploitative production processes is to threaten the production of labor power with interruption of the flows that sustain it. De Landa: Well, but the same point applies here: the conjunction of capital and labor can take place in different forms (scale, agglomeration) and it is clear that only the economic power of the former allows the kind of threat of withdrawal you are talking about: only if a firm is very capital intensive (large machines, large start-up costs functioning as barriers to entry) and if the process is based on routinization (the less skills a worker brings the less bargaining power he/she will have when it comes to set wages) can this form of coercion work. I am not saying that power relations are absent from networks of small producers but there the ability of workers to bargain for a fair wage (particularly if unions exist) is much greater and the permeability of the division between classes is greater too (if a typical firm has less than 100 employees and it is not capital intensive, it's much easier for a motivated, creative worker to start his/her own business). The point is that all of this is obscured (if not made invisible) by the blanket concept of "capitalism." As to theories of value: we need to go beyond the very notion of surplus value. (It's not enough to simply add the "machinic" type to escape the labor theory). Why just adding machines to "abstract labor" (read, routinized labor)? Why not also fossil fuels, starting with coal? And what of knowledge, skills and organizational procedures? And then, the main defect of labor theory here is to include supply factors and not demand factors, but the latter also matter, and so marginalist approaches to this side of the equation must be added. (Over the objections of Marxists who would rather die than include bourgeois marginalism in a theory of value). CTHEORY (Protevi): Okay, but even if the shift from an exchangist to a productivist perspective doesn't work for you, does it at least seem to you a fruitful way of explaining Deleuze and Guattari's tenacious loyalty to (some suitably modified) form of Marxist analysis, as well as their insistence on a systematicity to capitalist production? Or do we have to change so much in Marx to reach what Deleuze and Guattari say in analyzing things that their insistence on calling what they do a form of Marxism simply the result of their social position in the "gauchiste" (non-Communist) left of France in their lifetimes? In other words, their Marxism is a way of thumbing their noses both at neo-liberals and at party loyalists? De Landa: Well, frankly, I think Marxism is Deleuze and Guattari's little Oedipus, the small piece of territory they must keep to come back at night after a wild day of deterritorializing. Who could blame them for needing a resting place, a familiar place with all the reassurances of the Marxist tradition (and its powerful iconography of martyrs and revolutionaries)? The question is whether we need that same resting place (clearly we need one, but should it be the same? Shouldn't each of us have a different one so that collectively we can eliminate them?). I believe that the main task for today's left is to create a new political economy (the resources are all there: Max Weber, T.B. Veblen and the old institutionalists, John Kenneth Galbraith, Fernand Braudel, some of the new institutionalists, like Douglass North; redefinitions of the market, like those of Herbert Simon etc) based as you acknowledged before, on a non-equilibrium view of the matter? But how can we do this if we continue to believe that Marxists got it right, that it is just a matter of tinkering with the basic ideas? At any rate, concepts like "mode of production" do not fit a flat ontology of individuals as far as I can tell. But then, this is the part of my reconstruction of Deleuze that I am the least sure he would accept: in Difference and Repetition he cheerfully talks about the "virtual multiplicity of society" (using Marx as his example, of course) a term I would never use (since my ontology explicitly rejects totalities like "society as a whole"). CTHEORY (Mallavarapu): In your new book Intensive Science and Virtual Philosophy, you point out Deleuze's relevance not just to continental philosophy but to analytical philosophy as well. There have been significant differences between continental and analytical approaches to fundamental epistemological questions. This has formed the background to the so-called "Science Wars" debates between the realists and social constructivists. Does the Deleuzian concept of materiality offer a way out of the Science War debates? De Landa: Absolutely. You have to remember that constructivists have more in common with scientists (who are positivists, not realists) than with realists. Larry Laudan has explored the ways in which relativism (of any type) overlaps with positivism. Both make heavy use of conventions; both ignore mathematics and focus on language etc. Deleuze offers an alternative to both of them, and in my view, allows us to rescue the objectivity of science without accepting the myth of its achievements. (For example, we can accept that classical physics did get it right, within a limited sphere of reality, but not that it discovered the eternal laws of the universe). CTHEORY (Jensen): Finally, a question about your way of reading Deleuze about which it could be argued, rightly, I think, that it is highly selective. Deleuze, of course, wrote at great length about Kafka, Proust, and numerous other writers. He also wrote two books on cinema. And he has been received with considerably more interest in American literature departments than in their philosophical counterparts. But to you Deleuze's discussions of self-organization, the differential calculus, morphogenesis, and other scientific concepts and ideas have been much more consequential than his invocation of artistic ones. Can you elaborate on your way of reading Deleuze and its almost unilateral stress on aspects of his works relating to the natural sciences rather than the arts? How do you think these aspects hang together? And, finally, could it not be argued that your systematic selectivity is imposing on the Deleuzian corpus an interpretation, which not only could but effectively would have been quite different if other aspects of his work had been emphasized at the expense of those of your preference? De Landa: I agree that my reading of Deleuze is highly selective. The idea was: once we know how his world works (a virtual space becoming actual via intensive processes) aren't we in a much better position to understand the other parts? For example, in the theory of memory he takes from Bergson, one does not retrieve a memory trace from the brain, one literally jumps to another space (the virtual with its own always-past temporality). Now, without a realist ontology this would be a useless theory (if there is no virtual space where do we jump to?). But isn't it the same with his other uses of Bergson (e.g. in the Cinema books)? Or take for example his affirmation that all great art involves a becoming-animal of one sort or another. What would this mean if we cannot say what in reality these becomings are? (They are transformations not of organisms, like werewolves, but of the virtual multiplicities underlying the organisms). Or take the line of flight (also called the quasi-causal operator): this is the entity that builds the plane of consistency out of multiplicities. But without this definition (and the rest of the ontology) could we understand what it means to follow a line of flight in painting or music? -------------------- Participants Don Ihde is Distinguished Professor of Philosophy at Stony Brook University and author of thirteen books, most of which address issues in the philosophies of science and technology. Casper Bruun Jensen is a doctoral candidate in Information and Media Studies at the University of Aarhus, Denmark. His research concerns the controversies surrounding the development and implementation of the electronic patient record in Denmark with an STS- perspective. Jari Friis Jorgensen received his MA from the Institute of Information and Media Studies, at the University of Aarhus, Denmark. His thesis is titled: "Cyberculture, Science and AIBO -- a Non-modern View on Collectives, Artificial Life and Playful Quasi-objects." Srikanth Mallavarapu is a doctoral candidate working on STS and postcolonial theory in the English Department at Stony Brook University. Eduardo Mendieta is an Associate Professor at Stony Brook University. His latest book is The Adventures of Transcendental Philosophy: Karl Otto Apel's Semiotic and Discourse Ethics. John Mix, a consultant to non-profit organizations in Manhattan, is an independent researcher with interests in technoscience, particularly aquaculture. John Protevi is an Assistant Professor in the Department of French Studies at Louisiana State University. His latest book, co-authored with Mark Bonta, is Deleuze and Geophilosophy: A Guide and Glossary. Evan Selinger is an Assistant Professor of Philosophy at Rochester Institute of Technology. His latest book, co-edited with Don Ihde, is Chasing Technoscience: Matrix for Materiality. -------------------- Bibliography Braudel, Fernand. On History, trans. Sarah Matthews (Chicago: University of Chicago, 1982). Braudel, Fernand. The Perspective of the World: Civilization and Capitalism 15th-18th Century, trans. Sian Reynolds (University of California Press, 1992). Braudel, Fernand. A History of Civilizations, (New York: Penguin, 1995). De Landa, Manuel. War in the Age of Intelligent Machines (New York: Zone Books, 1991). De Landa, Manuel. A Thousand Years of Non-Linear History (New York: Zone Books, 1997). De Landa, Manuel. Intensive Science and Virtual Philosophy (New York: Continuum, 2002). De Landa, Manuel. "Markets, Anti-Markets, and Network Economics." http://www.telefonica.es/fat/edelanda.html#delandapaper Deleuze, Gilles. Cinema I: The Movement Image, trans. Hugh Tomlinson and Barbara Habberjam (Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1986). Deleuze, Gilles. Foucault, trans. Sean Hand (Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1988). Deleuze, Gilles. Cinema II: The Time Image, trans. Hugh Tomlinson and Barbara Habberjam (Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1989). Deleuze, Gilles. The Logic of Sense, trans. Mark Lester with Charles Stivale (New York: Columbia University Press, 1990). Deleuze, Gilles. Difference and Repetition, trans. Paul Patton (New York: Columbia University Press, 1994). Deleuze, Gilles and Guattari, Fˆ©lix. Kafka: For a Minor Literature, trans. Dana Polan (Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1986). Deleuze, Gilles and Guattari, Fˆ©lix. A Thousand Plateaus, trans. Brian Massumi (Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1987). Deleuze, Gilles and Guattari, Fˆ©lix. What is Philosophy?, trans. Hugh Tomlinson and Graham Burchell (New York: Columbia University Press, 1994). Dreyfus, Hubert. "The Current Relevance of Merleau-Ponty's Phenomenology of Embodiment." The Electronic Journal of Analytic Philosophy 4: Spring 1996. Hacking, Ian. Representing and Intervening (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1983). Hacking, Ian. The Social Construction of What? (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1999). Hardt, Michael and Negri, Antonio. Empire (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 2000). Hesse, Mary. Revolutions and Reconstructions in the Philosophy of Science (Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 1980). Ihde, Don. Technology and the Lifeworld. (Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 1990). Ihde, Don. Instrumental Realism (Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 1991). Ihde, Don. Expanding Hermeneutics: Visualism in Science (Evanston: Northwestern University Press, 1998). Ihde, Don. Bodies in Technology (Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 2002). Ihde, Don and Selinger, Evan. Chasing Technoscience: Matrix for Materiality. (Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 2003). Latour, Bruno. Science in Action. (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1987). Latour, Bruno. The Pasteurization of France (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1998). Latour, Bruno. We Have Never Been Modern, trans. Catherine Porter (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1993). Latour, Bruno. Pandora's Hope: Essays on the Reality of Science Studies (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1999). Latour, Bruno. War of the Worlds: What About Peace? (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 2002). Latour, Bruno and Weibel, Peter. Iconoclash: Beyond the Image Wars in Science, Religion, and Art (Cambridge, MIT Press, 2002) Merleau-Ponty, Maurice. Phenomenology of Perception, trans. Colin Smith. (London: Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1962). Merleau-Ponty, Maurice. The Structure of Behavior, trans. A.L. Fisher (Boston: Beacon University Press, 1967). Pickering, Andrew. The Mangle of Practice: Time, Agency, and Science. (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1995). Pickering, Andrew. "In the Thick of Things." Keynote address, conference on "Taking Nature Seriously: Citizens, Science, and Environment," University of Oregon, Eugene, 25-27 Feb 2001. Protevi, John. Political Physics (New York: Athlone Press, 2001). Wolfram, Stephen. A New Kind of Science (Champaign: Wolfram Media Inc., 2002). ==========================================================================="None are more hopelessly enslaved than those who falsely believe they are free...." Johann Wolfgang von Goethe Port:status>OPEN wildstyle access: www.djspooky.com Paul D. Miller a.k.a. Dj Spooky that Subliminal Kid Office Mailing Address: Subliminal Kid Inc. 101 W. 23rd St. #2463 New York, NY 10011 ----- End forwarded message ----- --- from list bhaskar-AT-lists.village.virginia.edu ---
Display software: ArchTracker © Malgosia Askanas, 2000-2005