Date: Sun, 15 Feb 1998 14:01:14 -0800 Subject: HAB: Re: BFN & co-origination Rob: Thoughtful posting! Thanks. First, some note of previous interest in BFN. Then I want to make a dialogue of your points and questions. ---------------------------------------------------- There have been two extended attempts in the Habermas List to focus on _Between Facts & Norms_, and these postings remain available at the gopher archive folders posted by Spoon for this list. The first group sought to get going in July, 1996, and got to presentations the last week of July, focusing on chapter 1 through mid-August (thanks to extended postings by Lois Shawver!), followed by a few postings on chapter 2, mid-August-to-early October (thanks especially to Barbara Korth). But the effort ended there (as far as the public list shows. Did off-list interchanges occur?) The second effort was born later that month, and got down to substance around the turn of the year, ending in mid-February, 1997. Some mention of BFN happened tangentially this past fall, too (Arto Laitenen, 9/25/97; my response to Michael Salter, 10/25 and 11/13/97), but no one bolstered my interest in focusing on it this year. I planned last fall to work through BFN around now (beyond the first 2 chapters and Postscript that I've read), but my reading schedule for Habermas has been pushed back by circumstance. I'm looking to early spring now (after a new reading of Habermas books from the 1980s, beyond the J&A essay discussed last spring). I want to post regularly to this list when I do work through BFN, if that is acceptable. But I really don't know when that will be. In any event, I hope you get some substantive response soon, in terms of BFN. The best I can do is respond in terms of my sense of Habermas that is based on work of the 1980s, which is presumably the basis of his applied work in BFN. ---------------------------------------------------- >[a] ...there is in all language the telos of reaching understanding; Without a doubt. >[b]...coordinated action ideally comes out of understandings and agreements based on the redemption of validity claims; Yes, but one should distinguish between tacit agreements and explicit agreements. In daily life, agreement (or interacting agreeably) is not usually based on the redemption of validity claims because the validity of understanding is commonly taken for granted, based on custom, etc. But disagreement is just as common, whereupon agreements have to be checked against the other's apparent misunderstanding. But even here, rarely do validity claims actually get addressed overtly. Often, persons can re-anchor their interaction without too much concern about whether misunderstanding is a factual or normative matter. Disagreement may appear as merely a matter of different understandings, partially factual, partially self-representative, partically normative. >[c] ..., where the authority of the sacred once functioned to regulate the spheres overseen by habit and custom, only mutual understanding can perform that role now; Yes, if "now" refers to specifically modern forms of action. The present is always a mix of levels of understanding, a heterodoxy of mythically-based authority (theocentrism in "moral" action) and modern authority (scientific justification in public policy). >[d] ... this mutual understanding now manifests as the law, the integrating agent of modernity; The law is ONE form of mutual understanding, more specifically: one form of normatively-based understanding (more specifically: procedurally/formally established normative understanding). But much modern normative understanding is not formally derived, and other modes of validity besides the normative constitute mutual understanding! Truth and goodness in modern understanding doesn't pretend to be reducible to questions of justice. >[e] ...the law's legitimacy then rests on the 'non-instrumentalisable quality' of intersubjectivity, which H opposes to Weber's thesis that the law's legitimation resides exclusively in 'political domination'; Yes, but I don't know that this is Habermas' view of Weber ("exclusively"?). >[f] to integrate a community which constructs itself as 'civil society', the law must be an instrument of coercion, yet it only has this capacity while its objects accord it legitimacy; Yes and no. Law may assert itself factually, as a enforceable state of affairs; but it may also assert itself normatively, as a fairly derived domain of responsibility and accountability. Between facts and norms, the law evolves. When its factuality is effective, this is because it is accorded legitimacy (we presume the law was properly instituted). So, yes, instrumental coercion only works as *law* (instead of brute force), inasmuch as the "objects" accord it legitmacy (I sometimes hate the constraints that traffic laws put on my freedom of movement--laws I had no hand in choosing; but I can appreciate the validity of these laws, and the legitimacy of the codification of them). But civil society must be based on valid processes of constitution and legislation, whose force is representatively (if not participatively) shaped fairly. Habermas does NOT believe that civil society can be "constructed" instrumentally. >[g] the law is to be seen as 'the medium through which communicative power is translated into administrative power'; I suppose this is fair to say of Habermas. >[h] we legitimise this process by way of the application of norms (universally obligatory, and therefore requiring justification) and values (historically specific, contingent and teleological preferences); A distinction between norms and values is very important. But norms may or may not make universalistic claims, and may be called to account in any case. Norms may be based in values! For example, the value of "liberty" is partically constitutive for democractic norms of political action. >[i] the law can not remain legitimate if courts accord values the status of norms because functionalism tends then to prevail over the democratic process of legitimation; I don't understand this; it doesn't seem plausible to claim that normative values simply imply functionalism. A constitutional value may have normative force in jurisprudence, just as it might in normal political communications. >[j] then the co-original private and public autonomy of the citizenry is no longer represented in the law; I enthusiastically support a notion of co-origination! But I don't see why--and don't believe Habermas claims that ---private autonomy should be represented in the law, other than formally: as protections of what is not the business of public representation. > [k] it is this co-originality that must be established if the book's intention is to be realised. I would agree that co-originality must be established if law is be ultimately well-founded. But I expect that it is not the intent of BFN to do this. It would be the intention of Habermas' work altogether to provide a fundamental sense of co-originality, involving moral-cognitive development and discourse ethics. I anticipate that BFN sets out to be a discourse about law and institutionality, which shows its connection to the larger context of Habermas' work, in which co-originality can make sense in Habermasian terms. >[l] the liberal model stressed the negative freedom of a subject abstracted from the market mechanism, while the post-war social-welfare model imposed goods, and consequently marginalised the freedoms upon which liberalism is predicated (the functionalism that follows from privileging values over norms?); Sounds right to me, except that liberal functionalism doesn't follow from privileging values as such over norms as such; rather, privileging *instrumentalist* values over other kinds of values (humanist? communicative? developmental?) in the conceptualization of normative sense is liberal, in the worst sense. >[m] how do we get to 'a third way'? I think that third ways are already commonplace in some areas of the planet, some domains of interaction, some economic formations, some cultural spheres. But these new ways are not readily named in traditional terms and lack the omnidisciplinary coherence of traditional schools of thought. Coming to terms with the unprecedented character of our planetariness is basic to my own post-"postmodernist" Project. The "third" ways cannot be comprehended "dialectically," in the conceptualist sense of this term that is attractive to neo-Marxists. >[n] well, let's look where we should - at the object/subject of the law; Let's not. I doubt that such a look can avoid implying a subject-object dualism, so I question that this is where "we should" be looking to understand third ways. >[o] we, the citizens, can 'adequately exercise [our] public autonomy, guaranteed by the rights of democratic participation, only insofar as [our] private autonomy is guaranteed' - ie. the autonomy of the private citizen and the public subject are mutually constitutive and therefore inescapably interdependent to the point of mutual definition. Yes! >[p] as we are the arbiters of validity, it is only in our communicative, ie. necessarily public and social, dimension we produce the legitimacy upon which the law depends - our role in this discourse depends on our personal/private autonomy - because we need to be free to assert ourselves in requisite rational argument. So the foundation of the law (administrative power) is an autonomous public, defined as free individual discussants deliberating on the normative. Yes, BUT Habermas doesn't locate law in administrative power. Rather, administrative power gains its legitimacy from law, whose foundation is an ideally automous public. >Some Questions: >Does this mean private freedom is defined exclusively as that degree of autonomy required to manifest communicative reason (is this what H. means by 'To the extent that we become aware of the inter-subjective constitution of freedom, the possessive-individualist illusion of autonomy as self-ownership disintegrates')? I'm confident that private freedom cannot be fully comprehended in terms of communicative reason, and I'm confident that Habermas would agree. But freedom that is not relevant to reason cannot be relevant to conflicts of freedom, for reason pertains to just that which may become relevant to communicative action (which may be most everything, especially for persons who have a thin sense of self apart from their intersubjectivity). Inasmuch as we are interactive beings--children of families and actors in public--there is an intersubjective constitution of our freedom. Inasmuch as our private freedom is apparent to others or engages others (or conflicts with others), it is representable to others, thus articulable, and therefore relevant (if not already involved) in the constitution of freedom, inasmuch as that freedom is intersubjective. *Enforcing* this intersubjectivity, through generosity of understanding and, if necessary, procedural justice, counters possessive individualism. But children ought not be reduced to their parents', peers' and teachers' views of them; nor ought human potential be reduced to public action. Creative and innovative persons depend on a rich sense of existence apart from what is intersubjectively recognized. >Does this [Habermas'?] line of argument rely on an ideal speech situation, and, if so, would the absence of this ideal context/procedure mean that Weber's notion of political domination actually prevails? The ideal speech situation is no more inaccessible than one's own capacity to sustain generosity of understanding and to commit to inquiry wherever it goes. This is not to say that the ideal speaking situation is nothing more than this. But, for Habermas, it is an ideal that is implicit to all communicative action. This implicit ideality of openness and fairness in communicative action can only become absent by force--through oppressive socialization and political domination. Unfortunately, distorted development is normal in much of the world. Even the most loving kinship-based ethic, if taken as sufficient unto itself, leads to distorting forms of understanding in a higher-level environment of mutual expectation that any mode of assumption may be questioned and sorted out mutually, as happens in modern education. The ideal speaking situation, in the long run, educes cognitive development, because it opens one to--and is open to--questioning at, in principle, any scale of concern (though time may not afford this in particular cases). >Does the claim that communication is the foundation of law usefully solve the private rights versus public goods dilemma.... Yes, I think so. But this involves a sense of self clarification that appreciates the difference between public stance and private background, just as law sets out to ensure a manifold boundary between public accountability and private discretion. >... (how would [communication] inform the judiciary in practice, and what differences might we expect in our legal system)? This is a matter of hermeneutics, or, to my mind, discursive hermeneutics (See my posting of 11/16/97 on "discursive hermeneutics"). >Does the whole argument depend on the proposition that agreement attends understanding? I'm unsure about your idiom here: "attends"? Understanding is the basis of agreement, such that one could claim that any argument depends on understanding--deepening and broadening understanding, in terms of our engagements, our commitments, our beliefs, values, identifications, hopes, and so on. To understand co-origination, though, I think one should focus especially on the character of self identity, in its plurality of intersubjective involvements that are integrated by a singular life history to which no one else has full access. At last, we are faced with our own sense of intimacy: Self-with, Self-in, Self-for, life, world, others, whathaveyou. Cheers, Gary --- from list habermas-AT-lists.village.virginia.edu ---
Display software: ArchTracker © Malgosia Askanas, 2000-2005