Date: Sat, 7 Mar 1998 13:45:30 -0500 Subject: HAB: RE: Performative Contradictions and Question Begging The Performative Contradiction Debate continues... (KEN) Eg. The criminal's action is existentially self-defeating since the strategic attempt to suppress the other in fact ruins (in the form of suffering) the life of the criminal; the trespasser >intended to do away with another's life but instead destroys >his own (J Bernstein, Recovering Ethical Life, 181). (ANTTI) This originates from Hegel's Philosophy of Right, and does not fit with Habermas's definition above (the criminal's action is not a constative speech act). (K's RESPONSE) Yes - but the logical structure is the same. Whereas the criminal destroys his life the speaker destroys their argument. >(K) My charge against this is that the argumentative strategy that Habermas employs begs the question. In other words the >case for developing the idea of a performative contradiction >uses one of its conclusions as a premise. It is the logical >equivalent of saying that God exists because God produces >real effects (William James). Logically this reads God >produces real effects therefore God exists. (A) No, logically that reads: Whatever produces real effects exists. God produces real effects. Therefore, God exists. >(K) The conclusion that God exists is used as a premise for the statement God produces real effects. It is a logical circle and completely incoherent. (A) Well, see above. Given the truth of the premises, the conclusion follows. You may dispute either of them, but if you don't, you're behaving illogically if you don't accept the conclusion. (I would personally qualify both of the premises, as James probably does himself. Of course God exists in a sense, like Santa does.) (K's R) Of course if God exists in the same sense that Santa exists this makes nonsense out of the substance of propositional truth claims. Ie. Anything that one believes is true, in a sense, even more so if they actual behave if it is true. Eg. Ken has a book with all the answers, hidden so that no one can find it, therefore Ken has all the answers because having all the answers produces real effects. Do I have all the answers or not? No - i don't - because NO SUCH BOOK EXISTS! >(K) This is the formulation of my critique: >Habermas must assume that rules of argumentation are true >and unavoidable (as a premise of his case) in order to >conclude that rules of argumentation are true and >unavoidable. (A) I'm not sure if 'true' makes any sense here. I'll try to reconstruct one way of arguing for unavoidability. At least some language games have constitutive rules, without which they would not be the games they are. These rules can be extracted from them through hermeneutic reflection and expressed in propositional form. (K's R) You have to assume here that the rules of hermeneutic reflection expressed in propositional form CAN actually yield the criteria for determining the constitutive rules - which requires the rules to be true a priori. (A) Now, does argumentation have unavoidable rules - is there a point at which we are no longer arguing? What is the difference between argumentation and non-argumentation? Habermas approaches it from the difference between convincing and talking into. He appeals to our "intuitive preunderstanding" (MCCA, 89) that you can't, for example, "convince an opponent of something by resorting to lies; at most [you] can talk him into believing something to be true" (90-91). (K's R) You have to assume a priori that the distinction between communicative and strategic action here is completely clear cut. If the two moments are entwined at any point then this falls apart. (A) He aims to find the points after which an exchange can no longer be regarded as argumentation, and formulate rules which make explicit our implicit preunderstanding of the difference. There are different domains of argumentation, such as legal, moral and scientific ones, each of which have their own specific rules which constitute them as independent domains - what counts as a moral argument does not count as a scientific argument. Habermas's work has recently dealt with such more specific rules of argumentation for the moral and the legal domains. (This is the status of (U), for example.) (K's R) Habermas must assume here that the distinctions between different discourses are valid. This can only be done in RETROSPECT and not established a priori (as Wellmer demonstrates). (A) Once we have identified such presuppositions of argumentation (by semantic investigation and generalizing from cases to rules), we can use them to look for performative contradictions. (K's R) How does one know that the identification of such presuppositions of argumentation itself isn't a performative contradiction? (A) I will return to your critique: >(K) Habermas must assume that rules of argumentation are true and unavoidable (as a premise of his case) in order to >conclude that rules of argumentation are true and >unavoidable. (A) This misrepresents Habermas's argument. It goes rather on these lines: 1) Certain language games have rules the following of which is unavoidable if one is to describe herself taking part in them. (K's R) How does she know this? And why should she care? - given the fact that the ideal may or may not conform to her vision of a moral universe? 2) Argumentation is such a language game. (K's R) How do you know when argumentation starts and the strategic struggle for recognition ends? 3) These unavoidable rules can be identified through hermeneutic reflection. NB: This identification is fallibilistic; the unavoidable rules are not unavoidably the ones that Habermas presents. (K's R) What would it take to demonstrate that hermeneutic reflection CANNOT identify these rules? You *need* to specify this in order to proceed empirically. 4) After the rules are identified they can be used to criticize those who understand themselves to be engaging in argumentation, but whose speech acts contradict the rules this engagement presupposes; this is performative contradiction. (K's R) Actually I agree with this. It simply requires a lot of presuppositions that I disagree with. 5) The unavoidability of rules of argumentation should not be confused with the unavoidability of argumentation itself, which Habermas also argues for. (Following the rules of chess is necessary for playing chess, but playing chess is not necessary.) This is not a metaphysical necessity, but an empirical one. There could be a human society where there would be no argumentation, but this society would be very different from ours, and the odds are none of us would want to live there (not because of the lack of argumentation but because of what it would entail). (K's R) Do I sense a 'best of all possible worlds' (just kidding)? >(K) I think that Habermas does this by reifying the actual >experiences of those who he charges (or could charge) with a >performative contradiction under a universalist interpretation >of language and language use - stemming from his Kantian >conception of 'man.' (A) What do you mean with the "Kantian conception of 'man'" and where and how does Habermas subscribe to it? (K's R) Moral 'man' in Habermas is noncontradictory man. Noncontradictory mem are identical - hence the noncontradictions. To demonstrate this statement I would need an army of arguments. Maybe I'll get around to it someday. >(K) This understanding of moral and ethical life >requires a "wider lens" than a narrowly construed discourse >ethic (REL, 183). Furthermore it is probably not desirable, or >consistent, to empty ethical life of its contradictions for the >sake of a "moral" argument. (A) Don't you contradict yourself here? First you say discourse ethics is too narrowly construed and then that its wider application would "empty ethical life". Discourse ethics is limited in its scope precisely because Habermas recognizes that such a discourse is not suitable for solving all ethical problems, only those of a particular kind. (K's R). I don't see it - it is narrowly construed such that, its narrowness, in reality, empties the contents of ethical life (ie. All of those wonderful performative contradictions). And yes, the problems it does address are the problems of noncontradictory man (a good superhero of sorts I think). Who wants to be and live noncontradictory mans' life? >(K) It is precisely our contradictory identity that we want to hold onto - because these contradictions make us who we are. In this sense Kantian noncontradictory 'man' becomes the antithesis of an actual (moral) individual identity. (A) As you surely know, Habermasian moral discourse is not meant to deal with identity issues. (K's R) EXACTLY. MORAL ISSUES ARE LINKED TO OUR IDENTITY INEXPLICABLY. This is why I think the moral domain in Habermas is a problem. >(K) And thirdly - all that a performative >contradiction can do is identify out fundamental beliefs - the >very things that we live and breath and wrap our lives and >identities around (REL, 184). (A) And that is a *problem*?? If indeed it can do that, it is a very powerful and important tool, don't you think? (K's R) This isn't a problem in Hegel - because Hegel *knows* that the performative self-contradiction applies on a concrete basis and not on a transcendental one (which he notes would be question-begging). >(K) He does so in order to defend his understanding of the moral domain in contrast to the ethical. Habermas does this >because he cannot have it any other way. Habermas is forced to generate the normative content of modernity out of itself, in a contradictory way, in order to defend his universalist postmetaphysical project and all of its contents. (A) Modernity is forced to create its normative content out of itself because it does not find any authority outside itself. Habermas tries for his part to articulate the elements of this normative content. This articulation is not itself normatively neutral, to be sure, but it aims to proceed as rationally as possible to leave room for as many visions of ethical life as possible. (K's R) Habermas argues that it is normatively neutral in the sense that procedures make some sort of 'weak' impartiality possible. Habermas *needs* (U) to guarantee 'weak' impartiality. However this is a kind of decisionism. One decides (on what basis?) to engage in this kind of reasoning. Habermas has chosen modernity. He argues that it is unavoidable. I disagree and I don't think I simply have to drop out of enlightenment to do so. Argumentation is a purified understanding of language and reason based upon noncontradictory man. If the vision of noncontradictory man is not a shared vision then there is no reason to participate. Only insofar as one wants to be a clone would one want to participate - and hence - since this appeals to a 'want' it appeals to something other than pure reason. As I have said before - Habermas discourse ethics is an emphatic ethics. And noncontradictory man is the implication of Habermas's moral imagination. Please don't take this the wrong way. I'm not deliberately being dogmatic and I'm not arguing AGAINST the force of reason to persuade (I'm trying to use reason to make my arguments). I simply think that Habermas's account has internal contradictions that need to be examined in order to illuminate whether or not his vision is the clearest. In other words Habermas has made a stunning case for universalism but I don't think it holds enough water to actually be successful. (A) I better stop now and send this or it will never happen. Correct me if I'm wrong, Antti (K's R) I'll let you be the judge of that. Please correct me if *I'm* wrong. all the best. Ken --- from list habermas-AT-lists.village.virginia.edu ---
Display software: ArchTracker © Malgosia Askanas, 2000-2005