Date: Sun, 08 Mar 1998 18:53:39 -0800 Subject: HAB: Understanding communicative action Thank you, Matthew, for your comments in <HAB: Understanding>, March 5. This was a welcome amplification of your earlier posting, which was a response (Feb 26) to Ken’s response (<Re: HAB: Imagining deconstruction>, Feb 26 ) to me, Feb 26. However, I disagree with your interpretation of the passage from Habermas which you use to warrant your suspicion of Habermas’ sense of speech acts. This difference of interpretation bears substantially, I believe, on other matters of recent postings by others, in particular the difference between communicative and strategic action which is so troublesome for Ken. It’s clear why you say that Habermas mucks up Austin, though I believe you are misreading Habermas, and I will get to this in a moment. But the larger issue is: Does Habermas misconceive communicative action? It could be that Austin was not clear about his own distinction between illocutionary and perlocutionary aspects. Indeed, John Searle has made a career of taking speech act theory beyond Austin, you know (I presume). And, you know, it is *Searle’s* speech act theory which is the basic anchor for Habermas’ formal pragmatics, which moves beyond Searle in _Communication & the Evolution of Society_(CES). It would be a great project to compare, contrast, and integrate the accounts of speech act theory in CES and TCA, but it seems safe to say that Habermas has not reverted to Austinian speech act theory in TCA. I have never much liked the terms ‘illocutionary’ and ‘perlocutionary,’ and I doubt anyone is especially fond of this Austinian coinage. The better we can convey the distinction in others terms, the better for interdisciplinary communication. It’s the distinction that matters. But this distinction, immanent to speech acts, is part of distinctions within communicative action between levels of action, such that a speech act may (and usually does) play in a larger scene of communicative action whose intent prevails over the intention of a given speech act. Accordingly, there can be, in a scene, differences between the perlocutionary effect that a speech act *has* and the perlocutionary effect that a speaker may have sought, just as acts have consequences, regardless of the consequences anticipated or sought by the actor. Whether or not an actor is acting strategically cannot be surmised at the level of individual speech acts, of course. Perlocutionary effects are likely in all events. One hopes that the other’s stance toward understanding is genuine, not deceptive. One hopes that actual consequences of one’s own action are satisfactorily similar enough to overtly anticipated consequences; but, then, one also hopes that overt anticipations or expectations genuinely express tacit anticipations or expectations (that one is not self deceived). So, it’s easy to confuse a difference between genuine and strategical communication with a difference that pertains to both, namely, illocutionary and perlocutionary aspects of “The” speech act. You write (quoting Habermas): “...it doesn't make any sense to imagine that someone could enter into a conversation with no intention ‘to produce perlocutionary effects on his opposite number.’" This view is due, I surmise, to (a) not distinguishing actions oriented to success from actions oriented to reaching understanding; and (b) not distinguishing the speech act (which always *has* a perlocutionary component, which may or may not have ascribed content in a particular speech act) and the larger scene of action within which a communication takes place--a scene of action which may or may not be prevalently communicative, may or may not be prevalently genuine when it is communicative, and may or may not have a given degree of consciously anticipated or expected effects, consequences or outcomes. Your quotation of Habermas above is taken from the longer quotation in your previous paragraph. Habermas “begins”: “"I count as communicative action those linguistically mediated interactions....” Habermas doesn’t say: I count as *communication* those....; rather, communication is one kind of action--the kind of action that concerns Habermas--within interactions that may be mediated in various ways--may even be communicative in various ways. But “I count as communicative action those linguistically mediated interactions....” Habermas, of course, strives to see a maximization of the organization of interaction by linguistic means, in the sense of linguistic language (not all of semiotics!) that his theory of communicative action elaborates profoundly. And he strives to see action-oriented-to-reaching-understanding prevail over action oriented to success. Inasmuch as *linguistically* mediated interaction is the kind at hand (a “natural kind,” I might add), it would be aims of action pertaining to the components of speech acts that would prevail in the aims of interaction *mediated* linguistically. Though all speech acts have a perlocutionary *aspect* (as well as illocutionary and locutionary aspects), linguistic *aims* of ACTION may or may not be oriented to reaching understanding (“illocutionary aim”) or success (“perlocutionary aim”). My earlier characterization of the difference between illocutionary and perlocutionary, to which you are responding, <U> 3/5, indicated a difference between (a) relationship and (b) orientation to understanding, which is not directly relevant to your exactly apt point relative to Ken’s reaction to you, your point being that the appropriate “logic” of discursive flow comes from the binding/bonding force of communicative action. While such boundedness, if you will, is represented by solidarity, solidarity is not the primary kind of belonging to which communicative action most pertains; primarily, it is kindredness, intimacy and friendship from which solidarity derives and is possible (I would argue, in Habermasian terms of the lifeworld). Someone with a weak (or problematic) sense of friendship will have special difficulty understanding solidarity. Someone with a weak sense of kindredness will have special difficulty understanding friendship. And a problematic sense of intimacy causes special difficulty in friendship. Action oriented to reaching understanding provides for openness in this continuum, in accord with the genuine telos of relationships which are always contextual (“context-dependent,” as you aptly indicated to Ken [<Understanding>, 3/2]), while the telos of understanding itself is primordially Open. So, your fine comments to Ken were an invitation to focus on the nature of communicative relations themselves, which is a dear concern of mine, and in the pursuit of which (such diction!) I will always be, along with all others, a student. In your comments to Ken, though, your attention was guided by a sense of action oriented to success. Not surprisingly, then, the prospect that understanding might be the telos of language wouldn’t become evident. This is not directly relevant to your point to Ken, since there you are trying to avoid metaphysical overtones by emphasizing the context-dependency that “telos” (better to talk about intentions) may have. Therefore, “this doesn’t show that understanding is the telos of language” (<U>, 3/2). Rather it indicates that understanding can figure into action oriented to success. A perlocutionary aim may involve the state of affairs of a given understanding that is to be conveyed. But the content of understanding in action *oriented to reaching* understanding is an emergent character of the interaction, not a content framed in advance by an aim to make shared a preceding content understood by one party (as pertains to instruction). But the difference between understanding brought to interaction and understanding resulting from interaction is always a difficult differentiation--one that only the participants can pursue, inasmuch as it matters what was “mine” vs. what is “ours” (No good teacher reduces teaching to lecturing, and no good course remains unaffected in its outcomes by the genuine engagement of its better students). Thus, though understanding can be a means to an end, the character of communicative action is obscured by indicating that “illocutionary effects are...a means to achieving perlocutionary effects” (3/2). Illocutionary *aims* of action--attending to the linguistic relationship of interaction--may achieve the perlocutionary effect of mutual attendance to the linguistic relationship of interaction; but perlocutionary effects (for the hearer) pertain to any speech act, as do illocutionary effects (quality of relationship). The illocutionary effect of speaking to you is usually that you freely give me your attention; i.e., a genuine relationship is invoked or educed. The perlocutionary effect of that *may* be that you feel imposed upon (It’s a bad day). One might *aim* to impose on you by speaking to you, in which case the imposer’s illocutionary aim of educing a relationship with you serves a prevailing hidden perlocutionary aim of upsetting you (By the way, you are mistaken in asserting, <U>, 3/5, that “bringing about a relationship between speakers is also a perlocutionary effect of a speech act....” If this is Austin, not Habermas, then the worse for Austin). But you might not be upset; the perlocutionary effect of the other’s illocutionary aim of speaking to you might be heard as a genuine attempt on the other’s part to have a conversation with you. From the perspective of a hidden agenda, the other’s illocutionary aim is normatively objectionable (he is an imposer); from the perspective of your hearing a genuine attempt to communicate, his speaking to you seems quite acceptable. Not feeling imposed upon, but not having time to talk, you courteously say you have ‘no time to talk now, yet how about...’. But, if you heard the other as he intended (to impose), you might curtly say you have no time to talk now, and leave it at that. But all this guessing about How One Is Likely To Act easily becomes specious outside of actual scenes of interaction (or reports of actual scenes). Within a success-oriented frame of mind, the “force of the better argument is ultimately still *force*” (you,<U>, 3/2). But for action oriented to understanding, the better argument has the *effect* of being persuasive. In a strategized setting of debate, the better argument has force *because* it better affects the views of open-minded persons; the argument better *effects* a view or change in view. This, of course, opens up an entirely different dimension of what open-mindedness *is*. Issues of linguistic competence, freedom from distortions of “reading,” fidelity to truthfulness, etc., can come into play with a claim that the actually better argument has not been appreciated. The unconvinced may insist upon the freedom to ignore good sense (not to mention standards of evidence, norms implied by one’s performances, assumptions of good-faith intent), which brings the unconvincing other (with the allegedly better argument) to possibly have to adjust interaction to account for the unconvinced’s confusion or even immaturity (if not--alas-- symptomatic behavior). I agree with you, then, that, in a sense, “all that is important to Habermas is that the effects of force are achieved through argumentative rather than overtly strategic means,” (<U>, 3/2), granting that “effects” are not reduced to “force” in a basically behavioral sense. Being convinced cannot be forced. It can only be effected or educed, as Socrates exemplified (notwithstanding the classical need for a “therapy of desire” [Martha Nussbaum] that Hellenistic ethics performed). As postings by Ken have shown, a focus on the primacy of solidarity causes difficulties for a self formative sensibility. In accord with comments above here, I think it’s important to disagree with you that “Habermas's project, I think, is ultimately just to account for and prescribe a remedy to the failure of solidarity in modern societies...” (<U>, 3/2). His project is at *least* this, to be sure, which is enough for your point contra Ken. But the primacy of developmental concerns in Habermas’ work doesn’t imply the communicative primacy of the political notion of solidarity. If anything is ultimate for Habermas, it is the evolutionarity of our form of life, which is presently an ongoing Project of Modernity, in which he is most concerned to contribute not remedially, but originally. Accordingly, a focus on solidarity (usually counterpoised to the existentially abstract notion of justice in the theory of democracy) plays into Ken’s basic misconception of Habermas’ philosophical project. We--all students of the human sciences and humanities--should understand communication in accord with the whole lifeworld context of understanding itself, of course, which involves a continuum of civility, solidarity, friendship, kindredness, and intimacy. As a Habermasian in the fullest sense (I hope), I don’t look to Habermas to do all the work for me (as Ken evidently expects of Habermas). *Because* I am a Habermasian in the fullest sense (ideally, anyway), I look to work with him, not (like Ken) to have Habermas work for me. To me, your sense of solidarity conveyed to Ken arises from a deeper sense of relationship than mere solidarity, for there is more to fellowship than solidarity, and you more than once show a fine sense of fellowship (though your paragraph, <U> 3/5, about what “Habermas should have said” is quite ingenuous, you must agree, and is best forgotten). You write: “Still, I take the really important point in his whole discussion of Austin to be this: "What Austin calls *perlocutionary effects* arise from the fact that illocutionary acts are embedded in contexts of interaction" (TCA I 289). What he means, I think, is that you can't do anything else by speaking unless your speech is first understood.” I agree that this is a really important point, but I disagree with your interpretation of it (which relates to a larger issue of the difference between communicative and instrumental action, which you address with Ken in a later posting). The point here is that given illocutionary acts are embedded in contexts of action, which may or may not be prevalently illocutionary. What Austin calls perlocutionary effects--pertaining to perlocutionary aims (in a notion of perlocutionary acts that is confused) arise from the actuality of levels of intentionality. This corrective--presuming I’m acting constructively here--all the more bolsters your shift of attention to the notion of performative contradiction. Though, I don’t know what you’re referring to by indicating “his ‘performative contradiction’ line of argument,” I quite agree that “pursuing strategic goals to the detriment of pursuing understanding only undercuts your ability, in the long run, to achieve your strategic goals.” However, there is a difference between performative contradiction (pertaining to interactive, public undermining of one’s *evident* stance) and self-defeating activity (pertaining usually to what’s not interactively evident), which your comment seems to basically represent. I note this--knowing I may be wrong--because the notion of performative contradiction doesn’t seem to be clear in other postings this past week by several persons. Performative contradiction pertains to an incommensurability between the assumptions of one dimension of communicative action and the assumptions of another. If I assert my affection for you angrily, we have an evident performative contradiction. If I ask for your view of an issue only to get a instrumental advantage over you (knowing how you intend to vote, so that I can determine whether I need to organize your constituency against you), we have a *non-evident* performative contradiction, an exploitation of my cooperativeness for your tactical advantage. Performative contradiction at the level of argument has been attributed to Ken very frequently, so it’s charming now that he’s so liable to find it in “Habermas’s” own arguments. [Let me say in passing that Ken this past week is making claims about Habermas that he made several months ago in interchanges with me, and at that time he admitted that his basic assumptions about Habermas were unfounded. Now, he’s back with many of the same claims (more or less), so I’m not optimistic about Antti’s yeoman efforts to counter Ken’s views. I surmise that Ken’s got himself committed to a dissertation strategy that he doesn’t want to fundamentally revise, in which case his performances here are just cut-and-pastes, more or less, from his strident notes. I regret to say I believe he is not genuinely open to other’s views (and has an ingenuine interest in Habermas’ work, not because he misreads--don’t we all!--but because he responds dissociatively to others’ careful attention to him, Antti’s posting of 3/5, re: question-begging, being my case in point).] Anyway, I agree with you that “you..can't maintain your communicative relationship unless you understand others and make yourself understood in turn (or at least give your partners enough of an indication that you're trying),” just as: “you can’t make yourself understood unless you create a communicative relationship” (me, 3/2). “It works both ways” (you, 3/5). Though, again, I disagree with you that “Habermas’ fundamental problem is...’Why is social solidarity breaking down?...,’” I quite agree with your picture of why social solidarity has broken down and the importance Habermas gives to communication for this important problem. Just as important, though, is the problem of innovating viable solutions to traditional social problems, solidarity or no. One could argue--as many in the New Left did--that a failure of leadership led to the disintegration of progressive movements in the face of social complexity, such that one say that the fundamental problem was the self understanding of leading voices in these movements (fraught with dreams of public power, military images of logistics, and nineteenth century notions of class). Not to open a can of worms, but the fundamental problem might be onto-theological as well. You write (<U> 3/5)--as if you were Ken?-- “Why should I care about understanding?” My answer is more than: In fact you *do* (MyGod, you’ve read this far!). In keeping with my contention that solidarity is one degree of relationship in a continuum from civility to intimacy, “I” care about understanding because it is in my nature to learn (I assert this precious view with research from clinical infant studies in mind; Daniel Stern, _The Interpersonal World of the Infant_, Basic Books, 1985). A disinterest in understanding is always a symptom of deeper problems with learning, calling for clinical interpretation. Inasmuch as your “grasp on Habermas is shakey,” may I and everyone on this list revel in a fellowship of shakiness. You write (<U> 3/5): “I'm not sure, though, that my difficulties with Habermas as you have identified them (assuming that they are difficulties:) are hermeneutical so much as exegetical.” I’m interested in focusing further on this distinction. Inasmuch as hermeneutics is a translational issue (in the broadest sense) and exegesis is representational, what makes hermeneutical perspectives especially relevant to the human sciences is the degree to which representation is always a translational matter. Such a theme has been basic to the growth of so-called “cultural studies” curricula in the past decade, I think. Let culturalists take to heart your closing point, 3/5: “...the important thing as far as Habermas is concerned is not that we actually get to a state of full and complete understanding....The important thing is that we *try*: that we show each other that we respect each other enough to try to understand and make ourselves understood to each other.” Thank you again for you comments, which have motivated this long posting. Gary --- from list habermas-AT-lists.village.virginia.edu ---
Display software: ArchTracker © Malgosia Askanas, 2000-2005