Date: Mon, 9 Mar 1998 21:40:59 -0500 Subject: HAB: Performatively Begging for Votes in a Contradictory Way Ok - this is where I stand, everything else is just window dressing: *** Every time Habermas accuses someone of committing a performative contradiction he commits a performative contradiction himself because his justification of the charge begs the question. *** (you can quote me on that) BTW - the votes are all in. 1 is support of Habermas, 1 rephrasing the question, 1 applauding the rephrasing of the question, and 1 rephrasing the rephrasing of the question. Thanks to everyone who participated - it really helped clarify things (I will avoid sarcastically drawing out ironic conclusions). Back to the fun stuff, > (K) At SOME point the conclusion, God exists, MUST be used as a premise in order to say God produces real effects. (A) I don't know if we can get any further with this.... (K's R) Because I'm right about this. Yeah yeah I haven't spelled it all out but the premise that "God produces real effects" *MUST* define what it means by God AND it *MUST* presuppose that God exists. If I get hit by a baseball bat this *necessarily* means that baseball bats exist. In order for God to produce effects God must exist. P1. God exists. Baseball bats exist. 2. Therefore it is possible for God to hit me with a baseball bat. P3. Being hit with a baseball bat hurts - it produces an effect. P4. I was hit by a baseball bat by God. 5. By hitting me with a baseball bat God produced an effect. Therefore C. God exists. P4 requires P1. End of story. It doesn't matter if I think God exists - God simply *must* exist in order to produce an effect. I see what you are saying though... (A) Again, this is just a logical point.... (K's R) Just.... > (K) What he is doing here is using the rules of an argument to show that arguments have rules. (A) I think we're getting closer to the crux of this debate. He is not using the premise "arguments have rules" to conclude that arguments have rules. First of all, that's not even ultimate conclusion... (K's interference) Then it is not an argument. (Back to A) ...he pretty much assumes it as established by Wittgenstein et al. and goes on to find out what these rules are. But it is still a conclusion functioning as a premise for another chain of reasoning and the charge of contradiction is therefore a legitimate one to make. (No wishful thinking, Ken, read that carefully. ;)) (K's interference) Yes - it is a contradiction - HASTY CONCLUSION. (Back to A) So, secondly, what are the premises for the claim that argumentation has (some, not yet identified at this stage) rules? Well, as I mentioned before, many ways of using language can be seen to be analogous to games, games played with the help of language, and games are constituted by their rules. (Further premises for these can be brought in if necessary.) From empirical clues, such as the fact that people frequently refer to what amount to such rules when arguing, we can infer that argumentation is possibly such a language game, and if we can with the help of this assumption identify some plausible ones, we are quite justified in believing that argumentation is a language game constituted as a distinct genre by having a set of rules. (K's R) Chess is a good example. You need a rulebook to place chess. You cannot deduce the rules of chess from playing chess... you must have a rulebook a priori. But in Habermas's game you have to obey all the rules in order to qualify as playing chess. But where did the rulebook come from? For Habermas it is a fact of reason, a development of nature. I like playing chess just as much as anyone else - but I also like to change the rules. I still play chess - but my chess partner and I agree that the rules are open to being changed.... sometimes we don't even use the rulebook because we think the author is confused about certain things. (A) In the above, the premise "argumentation has rules" wasn't used once. Yet all the time I made use of these rules. But since it did not figure in the deduction of the conclusion, it is logically irrelevant. It entirely drops out of the picture. If the conclusion follows from the premises, the only way to deny the conclusion is questioning the premises; there can be no logical fallacy any more. Compare it to the fact that without my existence, the argument wouldn't exist either. That, like utilizing the rules of argumentation, is in some sense presupposed in my making the argument, and quite bloody important to me, thank you. However, from the point of view of logical validity, it has no bearing. (K's R) Sure sure - but you slipped in the principle of noncontradiction as a moral guideline. What if Marcuse is right? "If dialectical logic understands contradiction as 'necessity' belonging to the very 'nature of thought' ..., it does so because contradiction belongs to the very nature of the object of thought, to reality, where Reason is still Unreason and the irrational still rational." Or what about Adorno - "Dialectical contradiction expresses the real antagonisms which do not become visible within the logical-scientistic system of thought" (both cited in Martin Jay "The Debate over Performative Contradiction" in Honneth, McCarthy, Offe, and Wellmer, eds., Philosophical Interventions in the Unfinished Project of Enlightenment). Jay, by the way (and I just found this article today) argues in a similar vein that I have argued - except he doesn't conclude that Habermas is begging the question. Fleming also agrees with Jay. And this is also where Benhabib gets off the Habermasian train of thought with her communicative conversation and where Braaten gets off with communicative thinking.... Likewise Jay Bernstein also tries to recast the debate because he is aware of the problems that such a charge causes....and of the premises it relies on... I think Bernstein is the harshest critique with Jay following close behind. Jay concludes that committing a performative contradiction might not be a bad thing - noting that all critique's of reason (however total they seen) have a place within debates about reason (in effect - welcoming a postmodern or dialectic rejoinder). Quite honestly I think that thought itself is a performative contradiction. Reality is always in excess of thought because of its creative character... > (K) Now yes, Habermas thinks this is possible - and he understands it as "self-clarification." (A) Yes, isn't that peculiar? Language can be used to clarify language and arguments to clarify arguments. At some point in the evolution of the species we developed a tool that can apply to itself. At moments like this I feel almost proud of being a human. (K's R) A contradictory creature to be sure. > (K) Can anyone help me out here? What exactly am I missing? (A) Logic. (K's R) Good. I wouldn't want to make the mistake of being consistent. (A) I'm sorry, I try to spare my one-liners to the next Schwarzenegger movie but I've put enough serious effort in this debate already, haven't I? (K's R). Yes. We both deserve candy. (Do you think anyone else has actually read this far?) > (K) ... If you cannot distinguish between an apple and an > orange ahead of time then you can't use an apple or an orange to prove anything. (A) And if you examine different shades of grey and find regularities in the way they vary, you can extrapolate black and white as the two ideal extremes. (K's R) Very good... almost there.... now you just have to demonstrate how white becomes black and how black becomes white mediated by the irregularities of grey... and then you will have demonstrated the dialectic that I am getting at here. > (K) Bring it to the (Habermasian) moral level and I will try to show you. (A) All right. Here's a country of four: two refugees (A and B) and two citizens C) and D). A. - I believe us refugees should have political rights in this country. B. - Hear, hear. C. - Why should we grant them when you don't even pay taxes? A. - Do you mean that there should be no representation without taxation? C. - Yes. A. - Well, I don't know. We don't pay taxes back in the old country. B. - Come on, the fellow is right. When in Rome and all. A. - I suppose so. OK, we'll pay taxes and take part in military service too. C. - I can see now that you are decent, hardworking, God-fearing men after all. All right, you can have the vote and whatever. B. - Ahemm... actually, we don't believe in God. He hasn't produced any real effects in centuries. C. - What, you don't believe in God! Oh well, I guess as long as you don't mind us believing, we can pursue our conflicting ideals of good life peacefully. B. - And we'll talk like this if there are problems about that. C. - Exactly. Now, what do you think, honey? D. - Anything you say, darling. C. - No no, what do you *really* think, honey? D. - These men have really convinced me. If nobody has anything further to say, I'll go and make some cake for all. We can split it four ways. (K's R) AWESOME. Excellent example - I really admire this kind of work - and it is work - because it is time consuming and often done with great pains... But.... I don't see at all how this moves beyond a (Habermasian) ethic into the realm of the universal. I have no good reasons to join such a nation state - what with taxes and all... even if they are going to share the cake with me. (A) I'll admit to that, but my point still remains that Habermas is not trying to argue the case for pure reason. Communicative rationality is situated rationality, and its results are contingent and always provisionary. (K's R) But no contradictions. Ken, who spent an hour typing up a response only to have my computer crash with the all-too- common "anything not saved will be lost" message plastered on my screen. This is my second response... the first lost forever (boo hooo... it was much more entertaining). --- from list habermas-AT-lists.village.virginia.edu ---
Display software: ArchTracker © Malgosia Askanas, 2000-2005