Date: Wed, 11 Mar 1998 21:50:39 -0800 Subject: HAB: Ideally discursive learning Antti’s postings of recent have been instructive, not only because they have been rewarding to read, but because they have been *instructive* rather than defensive. Habermas writes in TCA-1 (18): “The concept of *grounding* is interwoven with that of *learning*. Argumentation plays an important role in learning processes as well. Thus, we call a person rational who, in the cognitive-instrumental sphere, expresses reasonable opinions and acts efficiently....” Ken has gone to great length to defend this sense of rationality. It corresponds especially to the logical-semantic level of the presuppositions of argumentation (MCCA 87). “...[But],” Habermas continues (TCA-1), “this rationality remains accidental if it is not coupled with the ability to learn from mistakes, from the refutation of hypotheses and from the failure of interventions.” This seems to correspond especially to the second level of the presuppositions of argumentation, the “procedural level” (MCCA, 87-88). “At this level,” writes Habermas (MCCA, 87), “are located the pragmatic presuppositions of a special form of interaction, namely everything necessary for a search for truth organized in the form of a competition. Examples include recognition of the accountability and truthfulness of all participants in the search.” One is performatively contradicting oneself at this level when one appears to be committed to a search for truth, while being strategically motivated by concern for one’s “Image”--concealing, perhaps, a competitive search for truth in one’s competition to see who’s still standing at the end of a marathon, which can even become an obsession to avoid immanent nonconcealment. Part of the importance of Habermas’ repeated focus on learning levels in cognitive development, learning levels in scenes of interaction, and learning levels in organizational features of society is that communicative interaction--axially through discourse normally labeled “academic”--may be the medium for fostering mature autonomy in communicative action, universalistic discourse in interactive inquiry, and democratic openness in social organization. Yet, only the third level of the presuppositions of argumentation express the feature of discourse that is peculiarly oriented toward fostering the growth of understanding: the “process” level that has been called the ideal speaking situation. Anyone who thinks they can back away from reason with their self-image intact would have to accept being seen to back away from valuing the competence to speak and act, to question, to imagine possible contributions to communicative interaction, and the innate value of the opportunity to express oneself. Thus, one would have to accept being seen to back away from or dismiss situations where (MCCA, 89) “[e]very subject with the competence to speak and act is allowed to take part in a discourse[, ...e]veryone is allowed to question any assertion whatever[,...] introduce any assertion whatever[, and] express [one’s] attitudes, desires, and needs.” But nearing the ideal speech situation--the Nearing of discourse, so to speak--also presumes the sheltering of the being of discourse: “No speaker may be prevented, by internal or external coercion, from exercising [her/his] rights as laid down in” the above conditions. The degree to which this protective condition holds is always contingent, and usually to a disappointing degree. Such sheltering, though, is a kind of external condition for idealized speech; whether by internal or external coercion, such protection is a protection from inhibition. Correlate with this, and equally contingent, is the internal protection of the integrity of discourse which arises from the reflective application of the second level of presuppositions to the third: not all permitted interventions, questions, assertions and expressiveness will continue to be acceptable by others. For example, those who persistently exploit their freedom in the face of others will be faced with the norms of responsibility and accountability that belong with *mature* autonomy. The strictest test of this second level is brought by the reflective application of the first level of unavoidable presuppositions: evaluability of one’s semantical and logical competence. I don’t have a problem with persons who wish to exit from the land of science, law, and art, i.e., the EarthMind of modernity, so to speak, for life will remain interesting enough without them. Anyway, Habermas has never left behind his valuation of idealized speech. He just abandoned the attempt to specify it that was indicated in the essay “Wahrheitstheorien” (1973). Clearly, in his formulation of discourse ethics, idealized speech remains a vital feature of discourse. But he has never been insensitive to the realities of the lifeworld. This can be proven from work by Habermas prior to TCA. But it’s especially evident in “Remarks on Discourse Ethics” (which, by the way, includes a detailed response to Wellmer, which Ken is too busy to consult before playing fast and loose with his rhetoric). Even in the 1983 essay, Habermas notes (MCCA, 92) “Discourses...are subject to the limitations of time and space. Their participants are not Kant’s intelligible characters but real human beings driven by other motives in addition to the one permitted motive of the search for truth,” which deconstruction (of various genres) discloses through “diagnoses” of self-underminings of narrative (narratable or narrated) performances. In order to shelter and foster the potential of discourse, “topics and contributions have to be organized....[I]nstitutional measures are needed to sufficiently neutralize empirical limitations and avoidable internal and external interference so that the idealized conditions already always presupposed by participants in argumentation can at least be adequately approximated” (MCCA, 92). Whether the real conditions adequately enough approximate the idealized conditions or not is a matter of deliberation. “Admittedly,” writes Habermas, BFN, 322, this difference between idealized and real conditions “could mislead one into thinking the ‘ideal communication community’ has the status of an *ideal* rooted in the universal presuppositions of argumentation and able to be approximately realized. Even the equivalent concept of the ‘ideal speech situation,” though less open to misunderstanding, tempts one to improperly hypostatize the system of validity claims on which speech is based. The counterfactual presuppositions assumed by participants in argumentation indeed open up a perspective allowing them to go beyond local practices of justification and to transcend the provinciality of their spatiotemporal contexts that are inescapable in action and experience. This perspective thus enables them to do justice to the meaning of *context-transcending* validity claims. But with context-transcending validity claims, they are not themselves transported into the beyond of an ideal realm of noumenal beings....On the other hand, it is legitimate to use such a projection for a thought experiment. The essentialist misunderstanding is replaced by a methodological fiction in order to obtain a foil against which the substratum of *unavoidable* societal complexity becomes visible. In this harmless sense, the ideal communication community presents itself as a model of ‘pure’ communicative sociation....[But such a projection] does not detach discursive processes of reaching understanding from the bases of communicative action but reckons on their being situated in lifeworld contexts...” (BFN 323). The event of appropriation that bridges lifeworld and discourse, application and justification, is elaborated by Habermas in terms of his ownmost discursive neighbors as the essay “Remarks on Discourse Ethics.” I believe it would be appropriate to consider that essay to be near-to-mind when Habermas writes (continuing with the above passage from BFN, 324): “Settled but intersubjectively recognized norms, so long as they at least *can* be problematized, do not make themselves felt in the manner of external compulsions. The same holds for the symbolism of the language and culture, as well as for the grammar of the forms of life, in which socially related individuals find themselves. All of these operate as enabling conditions. Lifeworld contexts certainly constrain actors’ latitude for action and interpretation, but only in the sense that they open up a horizon for *possible* interactions and interpretations.” --- from list habermas-AT-lists.village.virginia.edu ---
Display software: ArchTracker © Malgosia Askanas, 2000-2005