Date: Thu, 12 Mar 1998 23:27:39 -0800 Subject: HAB: Re: Disclosure Antti, Thanks again for your very engaging paragraphs on disclosure, March 1 (<HAB: Disclosure>). That was in response--partly, at least--to my curiosity about “image-guided world disclosure,” used in an earlier posting by you (<HAB: Money...>, Feb 25). You believe evidently that Habermas accounts for symbolic power unsatisfactorily outside of the traditional, overt way that power is used, for example, in advertising, which might be called an external power of disclosure (or causality of the image?). Yet, the problem with Habermas is not clear. If there is not “anything in Habermas that would require the elimination of figural or poetic language as such” (Mar. 1), then it seems that it’s not openness to disclosure that concerns you, but rather an internal *power* of disclosure or causality that is unsatisfactorily addressed by Habermas. You write that “[i]n the Habermasian framework, this disclosure is a function of the lifeworld, and its being already ‘political’ in the sense of being influenced by different sorts of interests and relations of power constitutes an implicit criticism of Habermas's locating power as an independent ‘medium’ outside the lifeworld.” But this can’t be a criticism, unless you’re indicating tacitly that Habermas is not satisfactorily locating power as an independent medium *inside* the world, given your main interest in emphasizing (both 2/25 and 3/1) “that level of world-articulation that we stand on...preconditions functioning within” (2/25). Focusing on externality is not of itself to distract from a focus on internality. You would, then, be expressing that, for you, Habermas *isn’t* focusing enough on internality, regardless of whether or not his focus on externality is a deferral or displacement or, at worst, a failure of satisfactory focus on internality--notwithstanding that this “impurity” is a lot more durable “than many of his critics acknowledge” (3/1). Where, though, did you get the idea that Habermas wasn’t broadly and deeply appreciative of internality--from Bourdieu? A careful look at your sense of image and disclosure indicates to me that you’re considering disclosure as an auratic semiosis rather than cognitive constitutivity. From a cognitive point of view, the possible constitutivity of the image (as ontogenic prototype--Lakoff’s basic interest) can have much more power than the analogicalness that you are giving it (and associate with mere “metaphoricity”), allegedly contrary to Habermas’ sense of disclosure. Habermas’ concern for systematically distorted communication that made psychoanalysis an exemplar of what a critique of ideology faces and his pervasive cognitive orientation belies your indication of an implicit critique in terms of an exclusion of an appreciation of internality by focusing on external relations of power. As Habermas indicates in a quote I offered yesterday, the potential of articulability *is* the way that covert constitutivity is disclosable. Throughout his career, an *emancipatory* interest is expressed in the *ideally* psychoanalytic “discourse” of asymmetric power, as a way to comprehend what is at stake with the most elusive internality of the image, “systematically” distorted communication (mirrored in the *mirrorplay* of distort-ING relations). I believe that there is an intimate connection between “systematic distortion” in Habermas’ sense of the internality of ideology and the notions of deferral and displacement which are native to both deconstruction and the psychoanalytic concept of repression (from which Derrida has taken so much inspiration). The fact that Habermas is more interested in a post-”Critical” theory of democracy has no bearing on the merit of the project of immanent critique that may be implied by his work. I’ve been very interested in “metaphors and everything else rhetorics studies” (2/25), as it relates to Habermas’ work. I first gained a sense of “deeply sedimented images” through the work of Merleau-Ponty, several years before I’d ever heard of Habermas. In the 1970s, when Habermas first defended himself against the charge of inadequate appreciation of embodiment, it was in terms of Merleau-Ponty that he acknowledged the dimension of phenomenological experience (a number of years after his Inaugural Lecture, which postured his KHI project in the wake of Husserl). But perhaps the *Heideggerian* sense of disclosure provides an opening into the reality of the image that *is* unavailable to a Habermasian. But such unavailability is not implied by the fact that Habermas is not *attending* to this. That one is a lawyer, say, doesn’t imply that one can’t authentically love clinical psychology. At the least, Heideggerian thinking offers a more profound sense of *constitutivity* than a rhetoric of semiosis (Bourdieu?), and Habermas’ work is *at least* broadly and, I believe, deeply appreciative of *constitutivity* in our “form of life,” though his *project* is about deliberative democracy, in a phrase. Rather than looking for critique, one might look for collaboration among modes of discourse (see my posting of Nov. 2, 1997, <HAB: Cultivation of Humanity>)--to find a sense of marriage between intersubjective (“external”) and reflective (“internal”) inquiry. The challenge, then, would be to disclose an intimacy between internality and externality in reflective and discursive learning, rather than read externality of power as a marginalization of internality, as relations of domination seek. Let me, then, make a radical claim: There is no incommensurability between the work of Heidegger and the work of Habermas. Habermas’ polemic against Heidegger is a politically motivated stance against so-called “Heideggerian” criticism that expresses subject-centered reason. When I carefully read Habermas’ critique of Heidegger in _Phil. Dis. of Mod._, it was evident that the critique of subject-centered reason was at stake, not Heidegger’s thinking itself. “Heidegger” there is a stand-in for the genealogical character of poststructuralism. In fact, very few persons understand Heidegger very well. Critiquing subject-centered Heideggerianism has no bearing on the commensurability of Heidegger and Habermas. Even if it is accepted that Habermas believes that Heidegger’s own thinking is subject-centered (which, of course, it is not), it still doesn’t follow that the two are incommensurable, only that Habermas’ reading of Heidegger is incommensurable with both Heidegger and Habermas’ project of rationalization (in the genuine, philosophical sense). But, I no longer believe that Habermas really believes that Heidegger’s thinking is subject-centered. I’m too close to both Habermas’ and Heidegger’s thinking to believe that Habermas’ polemic against subject-centered reason could be anything more than a politically-motivated stance directed toward a 1980s German audience. I think that Habermas--a man, recall, who had been a student of Heidegger’s work--*could* not really believe that Heidegger never surpassed Husserlian consciousness. In any case, I know that the Heideggerian sense of disclosure is not incommensurable with Habermas’ sense of our form of life, whatever Habermas believes about Heidegger. You write: “With ‘disclosure’ I refer to the Heideggerian a-letheia, coming into presence, the entry of beings into the clearing of Being” (3/1). You know, though, that “coming into presence” is just a proximal way of referring to nonconcealment. The only time that Heidegger offered a course on _Being & Time_ was very late in life, to a group of psychiatrists. This was a strong corroboration of others’ association between Dasein analysis and the disclosure that is native to psychotherapeutics (Binswanger, Sartre, Boss, Lacan, others?). Accordingly, it is in the “Mitsein” of the interactive bond--most Momentously, one might suggest, in the therapeutic alliance--that awakening to one’s ownmost potential is most dramatic--here, *and* in the origin of the work of art, of course (which all philosophical work basically *is*--even given that philosophy itself becomes a stand-in for anticipated reconstructive scientific work). Since Habermas’ work is so artfully (*care*-fully) made--in the lineage of lastingness within the history of philosophy--it’s disappointing that so much argument can go on in this list without careful scrutiny of Habermas’ work (granting the adequacy of translation for the English commons). Anyway, you are quite clear about the breadth of interest in Heidegger from which your sense of disclosure is taken. Your narrative move back-and-forth between notions of early and later Heidegger suggests that, like Heidegger himself, you wouldn’t make a fundamental distinction between the earlier and later thinking (expressed, for example, in “Building Dwelling Thinking,” as well as _Time and Being_). Dasein is that through which Sending stems. But you’re not coming near to Heidegger’s nearness to disclosure by characterizing disclosure in analogical terms of the medial image, no matter how implicit that metaphoricity is posed as being. Constitutivity doesn’t work like modeling. It works like the light that gives things their bearing, like the mirror of the silent Other in a scene of analysis who embodies one’s own struggle (as is the case with Ken’s fiction of “Habermas’” performative contradiction). When I became wound up with the Habermas-Gadamer debate years ago, I came to the conclusion that these two friends did not really disagree with each other as much as they shared a commitment to making the issues that engaged them as public as possible. The “debate” was more staged than it was expressive of a conflict. Likewise with Habermas’ critique of Heidegger, I think. In any event, my own interest in Habermas happens to be fundamentally Heideggerian. "Art is history..." ...Gary --- from list habermas-AT-lists.village.virginia.edu ---
Display software: ArchTracker © Malgosia Askanas, 2000-2005