Date: Mon, 16 Mar 1998 20:12:23 -0800 Subject: HAB: Re: A Little More on Disclosure Antti asks: “Besides KHI and 'The Hermeneutics' Claim to Universality', where does Habermas deal with psychoanalysis?” In a programmatic essay, “Toward a Theory of Communicative Competence,” in _Recent Sociology 2_, Hans-Peter Drietzel, ed., New York: Anchor, 1971, Habermas attempts to apply speech act theory to the therapeutic scene. Though he didn’t choose to pursue this model further (for reasons I will guess below), some German psychoanalytical theorists have attempted to develop this model in some detail, with Habermas in mind. As I mentioned in a posting last October, an example, from researchers at the University of Münich, is _Psychoanalytic Practice_, 2 vols. Helmut Thomae and Horst Kaechele, New York: J.Aronson Publishers, 1987. One volume is theoretical; the other is a report of clinical and experimental research. Psychoanalysis is only addressed by Habermas as an actual example of reconstructive inquiry and discourse (as clinical theory) that serves an emancipatory interest. The emancipatory interest serves a self-formative interest (clear in Habermas’ very early work, e.g., “Labor and Interaction,”), which, in KHI, is a practical interest. But the practical (cooperative) interest does not capture the self-formative motivation of the emancipatory interest. This belief on Habermas’ part is expressed in his later (mid-1970s onward) focus on cognitive development. In the wake a emancipation (or for a lifeworld inasmuch as it is not dominated by distortion and abuse in the first place), the natural disposition toward learning and development is a keynote of Habermas’ thinking. This associates to why, in part at least, the discussion of psychoanalytic ego psychology in “Moral Development and Ego Identity,” _CES_, becomes entwined with an interest in Piaget, another example of reconstructive inquiry, as is Kohlberg (and regardless of what one thinks of the latter’s basic assumptions, his work remains an exemplar of reconstructive scientific inquiry). But the hallmark of Habermas’ concern for internality, I think, is his model of reflection as an internalization of dialogue roles. The profound implications of this is that precisely *in* discourse about communicative action and argument, one is also modeling, to some significant degree, the dynamic of thinking, *insofar* as thinking (or deliberation) *can* be modeled in accord with discourse. One does not have to claim that thinking can be fully comprehended as virtual dialogue (for, to me, its mirrorplay is surely, at heart, *not* primordially dialogal) in order to still gain great insight into, first, essential features of reflection / thinking / deliberation and, second, the place that communicative action (and, ideally, discourse) can have in the growth of thinking and deliberative action, by dwelling with the theory of communicative action and discourse ethics. As far as public life goes, *only* that thinking which can be communicatively organized can possibly have significance for others. To what degree communicative action can affect others’ thinking is always a contingent issue. Texts can only do so much, while they work best in living scenes of dialogue and embodied discursive interchange. So, I wouldn’t reduce Habermas’ sensitivity toward a disclosure of internality or internality of disclosure to his indication of psychoanalysis as an exemplar of reconstructive inquiry that attends to systematically distorted communication. But all this belongs together: emancipatory reflection, developmental learning, and internalization of communicative interaction. Yet the most obvious, the most compelling, the greatest example of an appreciation of the internality of disclosure is to be found here, in reading. One might easily take for granted the silent internality of this presence, and the sensitivity to internality that one hopes to find reflected. Gary --- from list habermas-AT-lists.village.virginia.edu ---
Display software: ArchTracker © Malgosia Askanas, 2000-2005