Subject: Re: HAB: RE: habermas and brandom Date: Sun, 23 Jul 2000 14:43:33 -0400 (Eastern Daylight Time) On Mon, 24 Jul 2000 00:05:06 +1000 Rob Schaap <rws-AT-comedu.canberra.edu.au> wrote: > Well, we needn't read "nonobjectively present" as "objectively absent", so, thankfully, we don't have to conclude that meaning can not exist. Meaning does not objectively exist, which isn't to say that it does not exist "for us." Meaning is purely subjective (we might say that meaing is the "fantasy-frame" through which we view 'reality' - but at the same time we should not be so silly as to assume that it does not "lean on" (anaklisis) objective reality. > What is the point of coming up with this autonomous category of 'imaginary'? Perhaps I misunderstand you, but we do not imagine with the things and events we are imagining, so with what do we imagine? Or are you heroically defending the (logically presocial) autonomous subject here? I think it is important to note the language is situated within a field of meaning. In other words, language 'in-itself' has no meaning (unless it is translated into our native tongue). This field itself is only comprehensible within language but not exhausted by it. The crucial idea here is that consciousness is grounded both linguistically *and* imagistically (we can detect in Habermas's essays on Kant and Hegel his real point of identification - Kant - where Kant's transcendental "I" is reformulated into a transcendental "we"). The problem Habermas faces is quite similar to the Sadeian trap that Kant falls into (as Horkheimer and Adorno and, independently, Lacan have pointed out). Any attempt, in discourse, to exhaust this rich imaginary will end in failure - which is why, in my last post of Kant, I attempted to argue for a shift in emphasis from consensus to the process of signification (the ongoing project of generating new 'metaphors' and forging new 'images'). Castoriadis talks about the "monadic core of subjectivity" which also includes an autonomous moment for the imaginary. There is something both true and false about this. First, these images don't come from just anywhere - they are assimilated through formative intersubjective processes. Second, at the same time, we can't pin the imaginary down linguistically (not completely anyway). So I wouldn't say that I'm defending a presocial autonomous subject here. The point would be that subjectivity is a "forced choice" - either one is socialized or one cannot become a subject, but the choice must be "constituted" by the subject as a free choice (failure to do so result in what Lacan calls a failure it internalize a master signifier - ie. an inability to situate oneself coherently in language - which is the definition of psychosis). Here we have freedom creating itself out of itself - hence my comment about creation ex nihilo. Let's take a simple example: chair. If I say "chair" we both likely have a pretty good understanding about the objectivity of chairs. But the meaning of the word, apart from the definition, is quite different for both of us - there is a web of associations --> hair, care, air as well as a series of images that appear to us the moment we try to picture a chair - wooden, steel... and all of the extremes of what we might consider a chair - a sofa, a couch, a table, a foot-stool, a the head of a department, a CEO... and so on. In effect, although we can agree that a chair is a chair, in this instance - a sitting apparatus - the "meaning" of "chair" has both conscious and unconscious associations that we can explicate to each other only to a certain degree. Ultimately, our "chair" is completely "our own" which "our own" pointing to the fact that what is "ours" is really the "Others" since the definition of chair was given to us, as children... and all of the associations stem from our subjectivization and significationization (ouch) of objective reality. In short, any agreement we reach about the "meaning" of a chair requires a double deception: first, we will quickly see that defining a chair is impossible, which then becomes instrumental in falling for the second deception, which is the definition of a chair that we agree on (we know it is impossible, but we suspend this difficulty anyway). In a sense, we tell the truth as if it were a lie. This double deception is operative in relation to the truth claims we make about chairs: which is understood not in terms of a formal system of semantics as corresponding with reality, but rather in terms of the existence of the Other, an ideal witness who transcends the particularities of intersubjective relations. Our agreement about the definition of a chair can only be purchased by suspending its meaning, which we know to be a deceptive lure, albeit constitutive of defining "chair" in the first place. There is a nice discussion of this paradox in Henry Krips book Fetish: An Erotics of Culture. ken --- from list habermas-AT-lists.village.virginia.edu ---
Display software: ArchTracker © Malgosia Askanas, 2000-2005