Date: Tue, 19 Dec 2000 23:06:18 -0800 (PST) Subject: HAB: Re: Habermas & Freud K: ....the idea, developed in Habermas's reinterpretation of Freud, > that language "is the only thing whose nature we can know," made in > his Frankfurt inaugural address in 1965, "holds just as true for > Habermas today as it ever has" (Whitebook 1995: 167; Habermas 1971: > 314). G: But the implication of this is that psychoanalysis, read after the > theory of formal pragmatics and cognitive development theory, IS a > very different "thing". Whitebook's point supports my stance, rather > than clarifying your disagreement. K: Exactly... [There] is something about the unconscious, trauma for instance, which fundamentally resists being drawn up into langauge. G: I disagree. But that's another issue (later). Whitebook's quote above pertains to a continuity of epistemic perspective on language, not a continuity of importance of Freudian psychoanalysis for understanding Habermas (or for advancing the critical potential of "emancipatory" processes, in which needs for cognitive *education* prevail, in JH's thinking, I believe). Whatever the context of Whitebook's assertion, it's undeniable that JH's analysis of language has been deepened and refined since his *interpretation* of Freud (What would it mean to call it a "reinterpretation", since interpretation belongs to the original inspiration of psychoanalysis, long before the Frankfurt School "discovered" Freud?). This deepening and refinement of the understanding of language (formal-pragmatic based theory of communicative action) happens within a discursive individuation that has left behind further concentration on Freud. Thinking about psychoanalysis *should* be cognitivized, so to speak--which indeed happens in JH's mid-70s essay "Moral Development & Ego Identity". His later work provides SO much resourcefulness for understanding that which early-on suggested neo-Freudian perspectives that I can't find practical a "systematic" (Frederik) focus on JH's reading of Freud. In fact, there's much reason to say that Whitebook's assertion above is invalid: Not only is it not the case that JH's reading of Freud was the venue in which he formulated his sense of the linguistic relativity of knowledge, but even inasmuch as this sense of linguistic relativity "holds just as true today as...ever" for JH, the *way* in which it is true looks nothing like it did in 1965, since JH's sense of anthropological deep-seatedness, lifeworld "background", cogntivity of world relations, and more have altogether transformed JH's sense of the "nature" that can be known--an anthropological, social-evolutionary, cognitive-ontogenic nature, anticipation of which is fundamental to JH's project and is, since 1980, very different from JH's view of linguistic nature in the 1960s. Consequently, the Whitebook quote above could be deemed counterproductive, since it occludes the importance of development *by* (of, in) JH's thinking, especially *about* developmental processes (as part of that thinking). So, again... K: [There] is something about the unconscious, trauma for instance, which fundamentally resists being drawn up into langauge. G: And again, I disagree. I don't just disagree, though. I *know* that the assertion above is false. The "talking cure" isn't about *representing" the unconscious in language (inasmuch as we're talking about the unconscious now--while psychoanalysis itself isn't basically about the mediate goal of erasing unconsciousness); long-term therapy is about working-through, in the richest cathartic sense of this, and working-through centrally *includes* language--includes linguistification of the sacred, linguistification of "the Shadow", etc.--but *basically* working-through happens *in the relationship*, the therapeutic alliance. This alliance does *foster* "being drawn up into language," such that resistance to a deeply mutual being-drawn may *also* be part of the working-through of the alliance. I'm sure that you agree. But so would Habermas! He does. He readily agrees that the phenomenality of experience is irreducible to linguistification. BUT only *inasmuch as* linguistification is possible can experience figure into *communicative processes* and thus *critical* distantiation or reframing or transformation into something *constructive*. K: I'm arguing that the ego - individuation - *is a symptom* - itself a defensive mechanism against being overwhelmed... G: Well, "the ego" is a very elusive thing. For Freud, it is merely the "I" (not itself a concept of egoism). The cultural notion of the ego is a very nebulous thing. To argue that the ego is a symptom simply expresses a discursive interest. THE "ego" of someone's lifeworld is a difficult thing to focus (like "self"), and defense mechanisms can surely prevail. But to argue that "the ego...itself [is] a defensive mechanism" is a special, if not extreme, interest in defensiveness, not a tenable theory of ego (self, I) generally, i.e., relative to healthy ontogeny or ordinary lives considered all in all. K:... it is possible to defend critical theory against the charge of being a critical hermeneutics (since it isn't reducible to interpretive inquiry).... G: But neither is critical hermeutics reducible to interpretive inquiry--otherwise it wouldn't be *critical*! What makes literary criticism *criticism* is that the *validity* of interpretation can be tested, according to principles of coherence, assertoric claims, evidentiary relevance, argumentative soundness, etc. Emancipatory critique can be tested, according to processes of enlightenment, lifeworld outcomes, efficacy of self-determined learning processes, creative productivity, etc. K: In a way, Lacanian analysis helps us to see that critical theory has a hermeneutic dimension which exceeds a philosophical hermeneutics, and has a scientific dimension which exceeds positivistic science. G: Habermas does it better. K: ... but I've argued ... that Habermas's defense of formal pragmatics begs the question - he gets caught in a circular argument, assuming precisely that which he needs to justify. G: JH doesn't merely "defend" formal pragmatics; he *defines* it, preliminarily explicates it, and greatly applies it in a theory of social evolution, discourse ethics, philosophy of procedural democracy, etc. His formal pragmatics is part of a fallibilistic *research program* that, in part, *hypothesizes* what it *advocates*. The tenability of this metatheoretical work depends on *knowledge" about language--what research indicates about our linguisticality. And let me tell you: a lot of research supports the tenability of linguistics having a cognitive basis. ------------------------------------------- K: > > ....Habermas writes: "As can be shown through the example of > > psychoanalysis, as interpreted in terms of communication theory, > > the two procedures of reconstruction and of self-critique can still > be brought together within the framework of one and the same theory" > (Habermas 1987:300). G: > Yet, this "one and the same" is the theory of communicative action, > not a basically psychoanalytic reading of the communicative potential > for learning and emancipation from distortions. K: I read this to mean that a theory of communicative action clarifies what is at stake in psychoanalysis.... G: JH's theory provides for a clarification that Freud's could not. Isn't the point above that psychoanalysis provides AN *example* in practice of what, in theory, *was not* brought together within a framework *prior* to JH's theory? It's not about Freudian psychoanalysis (a cognitivist psychoanalysis makes a better example); it's not even basically about psychoanalysis. It's about the *theory* of reconstructive critique, which JH prefers to explicate in terms of moral developmental research, by the way. K: ...the reconstructive (whereby the analyst draws on the unconscious rule systems of a given methodology) and the self-critical (the actual procedure of dialogue). G: How reconstruction works in psychoanalysis is, I think, a very subtle thing, less concerned with the method of the madness (to be coy) than with educing the integrative striving of the self to Live On fruitfully--which dissolves the madness. IN dialogue, mutual (allied) reconstruction of madness and precedent striving are brought together into reflective Moments (which are often very intense) of recognition and dissolution that releases one into their ownmost potential for (re) constructing a life. In education "teachable mooments" do things that can be quite dramatically consequential, too. But transposition of such entwinements of reconstructive recognition / reflection into *methodological* processes of disciplinary and discursive fruitfulness is not a straightforward mapping of the psychotherapeutic example into communicative life, which JH has emphasized and re-emphasized. K....Habermas needs psychoanalysis or at least psychoanalytic concepts to vindicate his claim that the unconscious is solely derived from language G: One shouldn't be surprised that psychoanalysis is the basis for explicating a psychoanalytic concept. But he doesn't claim that "the unconscious is solely derived from language," just as he doesn't claim that systematically distortive processes in society are all linguistic. But ONLY inasmuch as distortion can be *translated* into articulations can its counterproductive (if not destructive) power be eventually annuled. K: ...we should also note that Habermas's reading of Freud is likely one that led to his insight about systematically distorted communication, at least it is in his reinterpretation of Freud that he makes the most sustained argument about this. G: May be. Maybe the insight was cumulative, coming from Nietzsche (who was Freud's inspiration and as much the center of JH's analysis in KHI as Freud) or Marx's false consciousness or Hegel's notion of the slave morality or Kant's notion of compelling antinomies or Socratic disabusing one of their common sense presumptions. What's important is that distortive social processes that have taken on a systematic character is a critical sociological notion that cannot be derived from psychoanalysis. Even Freud's excursions into cultural critique are not extrapolations from therapeutic practice (likewise for Jung's notion of Collective Unconscious). At a point, Freud, Jung, and Habermas are all social critics making claims about general social processes, and there is no way that Freud or Jung would have become Habermasians (had they found the Fountain of Youth). K: In any event, it would be bad faith on Habermas's part to use a psychoanalytic-inspired analysis as a critique of Foucault that isn't at all related to or dependent upon any of the concepts of psychoanalysis. G: Using critical concepts isn't the same as advocating one's fundamental views. Foucault invites psychoanalytic forms of critique. Kantians may invite Hegelian forms of critique by a Marxist or Heideggerian. Derrida is a grand master of psychoanalytic language, but he's not basically Freudian or even psychoanalytic (just as the Heideggerian deconstruction of metaphysical subjectivity isn't basically motivated by critique of metaphysics). Doing critique is a matter of bringing to bear the most appropriate notions *immanently* for the sake of moving discourse to a new stage of inquiry. In education, one takes the stance of the next stage of learning, relative to the student's present "zone of proximal development" (Vygotsky). Critique is relative to its "object". K: In effect, the fact that he is using his reinterpretation of Freud against contemporary social-theoretical frameworks is enough evidence for me that it is "very much... to some degree" part of Habermas's critical social theory... G: But using psychoanalytical concepts is not the same as merely using an interpretation of Freud. Making psychoanalytical concepts part of critical social theory is itself part of a *philosophical* project that is inconceivable from a psychoanalytic point of view. But earlier, your "very much...to some degree" was a claim about Habermas' relationship to Freud, not his use of psychoanalytic concepts in critique. And I said *that* is untenable. ------------------------------- K: If critical theory is an attempt to contribute to a communicatively productive social life, doesn't critical theory have to know what a communicatively productive social life is or looks like? G: No, since the success of critique is not to advance a particular sense of the good life, but to broaden (and deepen) the community's ownership in questioning and formulating, which includes democratization of access to education and evoking effective ownership in consequential social decision-making processes, etc. You may disagree that this is what critique should aspire to do, but that very disagreement is the *kind* of communicative actvity that implies the critical values you'd be rejecting. K: And if that is the case, how did critical theory acquire knowledge about this life? G: Isn't that like asking how a child acquired interest in learning? If the child doesn't know, is the desire to learn thereby undermined? *Critical Theory* acquired this "knowledge" as the history of philosophy acquired this knowledge, you know JH claims. K: As far as I can see, simply because enlightenment posits a telos: autonomy, solidarity and so on, doesn't mean it would be a 'good thing' to achieve it. G: And freedom's just another word for nothing left to lose. K: The 'dream' of the enlightenment is autonomy and happiness... G: Ah, sooo right. K: ...but this dream is a dream - a wish-fulfillment. G: No, it's a lot of work. K: Fundamentally, it is unrealizeable. G: Since you can "fundamentally" only speak for yourself, let me happily hope that, fundamentally, you're wrong. As for the rest of humanity, hope is ultimately all we have. Less than ultimately, we have lots of resources. We need leadership (Christien? Bush?). We need Time (Hurry on, educational reform! Hurry on, constitutional democracy! Hurry on, health sciences! Etc.) [Hurry on, bioscience! I want to be productive beyond 100!] K: Habermas, in KHI calls for an 'exact fantasy' - this is precisely what we need to talk more about. One of the chief characteristics of fantasy is that we do everything in our power to avoid its fulfillment - G: "We". K: That's what makes it a fantasy: the idea that we can't have it. G: No, no. What makes it fantasy is simpler: that it expresses unfulfillED desire, much of which IS attainable. You're not distinguishing degrees of prudence in fantasy.You might fantasize as a kid that you'll one day be a great scientist by 40, and this can at least result in being a very good scientist by 30. You wanna be great, too? 50% sweat, 45% luck. And the gamble's all the fun (and exhaustion). K: And whenever we have reached it, we've ended up with a high degree of violence and destruction. G: So many bulls in china shops. But there is progress! Crime is not an inevitable correlate of a good economy (rising waters do raise a lot of boats, even if never enough); war isn't an inevitable aspect of modernization ("Democracies" don't declare war on each other--or turn to civil war in contested elections--though fairness is never complete). K: Gary, thanks for your instructive thoughts. They are warmly appreciated. G: Great! Thanks for saying that. For me, constructive disagreement is nearly as appealing as consensual collaboration--not that I care much for generally disagreeable styles of interaction. Anyway, high levels of disagreement can be sublime learning experiences (Response is not mere re-presentation, but articulation!). Discursive disagreement *can* be very constructive. Even contentiousness can be a Gadamerian play of light on water. Fantasy Cheers! Gary. __________________________________________________ Do You Yahoo!? Yahoo! Shopping - Thousands of Stores. Millions of Products. http://shopping.yahoo.com/ --- from list habermas-AT-lists.village.virginia.edu ---
Display software: ArchTracker © Malgosia Askanas, 2000-2005