Date: Thu, 22 Feb 2001 13:27:31 -0800 (PST) Subject: Re: HAB: re: Lifeworld & fallibilism Bill: I think we agree more than disagree on lifeworld articulability. I’ll mostly skip over what I agree with, from your posting yesterday, in order to save space. Earlier, I disagreed that [BH] "the lifeworld cannot be questioned without performative contradiction" (#39) by claiming that Habermas was making a more limited claim (that we both might agree with?): [G] “ ...one cannot at the same time presume something performatively and take an hypothetical stance toward that same something” (#47). But you disagree: [B] ...one can "at the same time presume something performatively and take an hypothetical stance toward that same something." The ability to do so is the basis of the experimental attitude (fallibilism). [G] Immediately following my assertion above, I elaborated at some length what I meant, in terms of *at the same time*. I might, then, have revised my assertion: One cannot at the same time presume something performatively at time T and take an hypothetical stance toward that something at the same time. This could be read as a logical point, except that the logical reading is an entailment of a pragmatic point: One can’t employ something and at the same time examine it. One can’t use a term and mention it at the same time. One can’t look at X-at-time-T and simultaneously represent that act of looking. I believe that this kind of condition is what Habermas means by “performatively”. Of course, there’s a big difference between (1) performative presumptions that are merely immanent to an act and (2) performative presumptions that are constitutive of lifeworld cognitivity. The degree to which cognitivity can be thematized is a very questionable area of inquiry and thinking. Habermas appears to be so clear about the unquestionability of the background that I have to read him as tacitly thinking of the Background prior to highly postconventional thinking about the Background, since indeed one can say a great deal about the Background, and in this sense, I agree with you that “the ability to do so is the basis of the experimental attitude (fallibilism).” But reconstructive inquiry is an entirely different kind of endeavor from reflective analysis of one’s own presumptions (which is phenomenological). Phenomenological analysis may achieve a great deal--how much, though, is very questionable. But one can’t simultaneously act and reflect on that same action (which is a different action). The degree to which the Background (beyond any given activity) is highly (deeply) elusive is the question. Reconstructive inquiry never pretends to be phenomenology (rather: Philosophy is strapped with the challenge of finding the bridge between phenomenology and theorized /systemic inquiry). [B] Restated, my principle is that the lifeworld *as a whole* cannot be questioned without performative contradiction. [G] I’m sure Habermas agrees, since he says this in his discussion of the Background in _On the Pragmatics of Communication_. And you provide good citations from other sources. So, you don’t have to qualify your view as an “extrapolation”. However, your very astute discussion doesn'’t keep clear the distinction between reflection on one’s own activity (phenomenology) and theorized inquiry into the presumptions of observed action. [B] One can take a fallibilistic stance toward the entire lifeworld-- but only from a theoretical, 3rd person point of view. (See PDM, p. 299; see also OPC, p. 430). And it is precisely this limitation that makes it impossible to question the entire lifeworld, as the irreplaceable background of our practices, without performative contradiction. [G] I largely agree, but--to advance the issue, maybe--a second-person perspective is relevant to reflection as well (so too for the interpretive dimension of “behavioral” science, inasmuch as we are interpreting the *actions* of “subjects” that we are WITH). Both personal and theorized interpretation have the second- and third-person perspectives available, but cannot have these in the same way. A second-person view on my own action is fundamentally different from “your” own view of my action, and my endeavor to take a third-person stance can’t be truly that (except through special training, as with the psychoanalyst’s understanding of counter-transference and projective identification--which anyway never frees itself wholly from first- and second-person stances--and so, too, for science). Accordingly, the issue of the articulability of the lifeworld is different for the performer and the scientist. Earlier, I had been thinking about the situation of the performer, which can grow to understand quite a bit about the Background. Again, it’s quite the issue how much can be understood *in general*, i.e., about the lifeworld as a “whole”. So, I would agree with your points, but suggest that you’re introducing a different kind of focus. Methodological fallibilism and existential articulability (the basis for reflective fallibilism) are different kinds of issues. I failed to maintain this distinction, so your points are complementary. You’re back with the existential perspective when you continue next that: [B] To take such a stance, I must give up the practical meaning of any particular segment that might be questioned in relation to a particular action. Habermas apparently thinks that I can take such a theoretical stance toward the lifeworld as a whole, that I can bracket off my own immersion in a particular lifeworld context of action long enough to get a glimpse of the whole thing (by means of, I think, presuppositional analysis). [G] I disagree. Even your quotes from JH (deleted above) suggest the contrary. A key issue for JH is the inaccessibility of the Background. I agree, though, that JH believes that, inasmuch as articulability is possible.... [B] This happens, on his account, as specific validity domains emerge from the lifeworld--an outerworldly domain of truth, an innerworldly domain of experience, and a social world of norms. It is within these emergent domains that we are able to articulate and question the suppositions of either (1) particular contexts of action (hermeneutically) or (2) the kinds of suppositions that must be present in the lifeworld in general (theoretically).) But, on his view, we cannot do both simultaneously, and we cannot question the presuppositions of all particular contexts of action. [G] Yeah, this was the kind of point that I had in mind. You put it very well. [B] Someone might argue that, in principle at least, we could thematize any of those situations, so those presuppositions are in principle articulable and hence fallible. [G] I was moving in this direction, in postings of the past weekend. [B] Given enough time, we could articulate all presuppositions. [G] This is the kind of statement I’m wondering about. Just how far *can* “one” go? I don’t know. What *are* the boundaries of postconventional learning about one’s Background? [B] But this [all-ness] would be mistaken, because the lifeworld must be understood holistically. "As a totality that makes possible the identities and biographical projects of groups and individuals, it is present only prereflectively." (PDM, 299) [G] Indeed. So, I’m at the point where I need to directly confront JH’s position in an extended manner. I tend to disagree with “present only”, in the quote above. He seems to not actively appreciate the difference between preconventional presence and his own postconventionality, as pertains to the articulability of the lifeworld. But this is an open issue for me, regarding what JH thinks. It seems clear that I’m either deluded or I may genuinely disagree with JH. I need to work this out. I wish that I could disagree with you more (it’s more interesting for others), but... [B] When we thematize a lifeworld segment in order to question its particular presuppositions, and alter through argumentation any of those presuppositions, we must recognize that, in principle, other unthematized presuppositions also may undergo change, and these changes cannot be known except in the context of other thematizations; etc. [G] My issues is: What can learnability hope for, in this undergoing? [B} If I am correct, [...postconvention thinkers...] are able to see more of their experience as fallible. They will consequently be more open to processes of argumentation. [G] Or, more to my point: more open to the scale of learnability--which eventually reaches best available perspectives and available means within the discourse community; and one is then learning at the Edge, pushing the envelope of learnability. [B] But it does not follow, I think, that the prethematic lifeworld will be reduced (meaningfully). [G] It seems that JH would agree with you. Yet, it's meaningful to question the unconditionality of such claims. So much *can* be thematized. [B] This is because the lifeworld is vague in the philosophical sense of vagueness; it remains a "vast and incalculable web" (TCA2, p. 131). [G] VERY good point, ultimately speaking. So: How vague must we remain? How far can learnability go? How articulated can lifeworldness become? I am still asking, in my own self formation, feel so far to go. Thanks! Gary __________________________________________________ Do You Yahoo!? Yahoo! Auctions - Buy the things you want at great prices! http://auctions.yahoo.com/ --- from list habermas-AT-lists.village.virginia.edu ---
Display software: ArchTracker © Malgosia Askanas, 2000-2005