Date: Sun, 12 Jan 2003 22:29:51 -0800 (PST) Subject: HAB: Going beyond tolerance through humanism Sunday This is a detailed discussion of Habermas's recent article "Intolerance and discrimination," from the International Journal of Constitutional Law (1:1, Jan '03), which has been uploaded to the "Files" area of the Yahoo! Habermas site. Thanks in advance for your time; this is a dense discussion, I confess, but it is closely attuned to the specifics of Habermas's discussion. ----------------------------------------------- 'Tolerance' is a distasteful notion. At best it's a plateau in a learning process out of discrimination toward appreciation, understanding and genuine belonging together. So, while I do appreciate Habermas' explication of the character of tolerance--finally providing a sense of the difference between genuine and condescending tolerance--I think that there's a way out of the "demands" of "cognitive dissonance" (12) that allows for religious multiculturalism beyond toleration. "Toleration first becomes necessary when one rejects the convictions of others" (3). This doesn't seem right: One rejects the convictions of others in discrimination, so what makes toleration necessary must be something else. Let me call this, as neutrally as I can, the *interest* (whether need or desire) in living together constructively, or more succinctly: the basic human interest. *Given* the basic human interest, *the necessity of rejecting* the convictions of necessary and unavoidable others (inhabiting the same economic locale) makes tolerance necessary. Fundamentally, it is *cognitive dissonance* AS NECESSARY (or unavoidable) that, GIVEN the basic human interest, compels tolerance. So, understanding tolerance is a matter of understanding (a) the compellingness of the basic human interest and (b) the contingencies of cognitive dissonance that appear to be necessary. "[W]e can talk of toleration only if the parties involved base their rejection on a *cognitive conflict between beliefs and attitudes that persists for good reasons" (3), which covers (b) above, but "good reasons" are twofold: (a) the realized basic human interest, arising in the face of accepted cohabitation and (b) "good reason" assays of necessity in cognitive dissonance. Good reason for necessary cognitive dissonance (e.g., inability to understand the other at all) alone is compatible with discrimination; but peaceful cohabitation, in the basic human interest (constructive life on shared ground) is incompatible with discrimination. But one might argue that good reason for cognitive dissonance is NOT compatible with discrimination, but keep in mind that Habermas stipulates that tolerance requires a dissonance which compels *rejection* of the convictions of the other, which IS compatible with discrimination. "We do not need to be tolerant if we are indifferent toward other beliefs and attitudes or even if we appreciate otherness" (3). What turns rejection into tolerance is appreciation of the basic human interest: We need/desire constructive living with the other (whose beliefs and attitudes we MUST reject). What is the historical basis for appreciation of the basic human interest? Habermas claims---and will genealogically argue---that the "shared standard" of "equal inclusion" or "non-discrimination...first provides the moral and constitutional reasons for toleration" (3-4), but what is the basis of the standard which *becomes* shared? I pose this question as: What is the origin of the basic human interest? "On [the] basis of a normative consensus, [necessary cognitive dissonance] can be neutralized in the social dimension of equal treatment," (4) but what is the basis of this normative consensus and what is the nature of its content? As "moral" reason, one could richly address the issue as a matter of education and the cultural conditions of progressive education. But Habermas doesn't take this direction, rather: moral reason is a pretext for law. Of course, Habermas would emphatically approve of educational means to appreciation of equality, but what he advocates is a matter of law, clearly as a compensation for the rejectionist necessities of tolerance that might be dissolved through education. But Habermas's legalist approach also favors portrayal of the "moral" issue as primarily one of enforced equality (and justifiable coercion), rather than appreciation of the basic human interest (and examination of ways to educationally and culturally promote this appreciation---an appreciation which provides, I would argue, a basis for getting beyond the "necessity" of cognitive dissonance, whereas a regulatory regime of equality does not. I see regulatory regimes as *merely* compensatory, thereby losing their mandate in proportion to assessable educational progress. Habermas would approve of this, I believe. But his thinking apparently doesn't provide for this. He apparently would be ready to retire from discourse once the regulatory regime is universal). The importance of the basic human interest for, first, compelling tolerance and, then, getting beyond tolerance, implies a different sense of genealogy than Habermas provides. Rather than "the struggle for religious tolerance becom[ing] the model for multiculturalism," I think that the struggle for cultural freedom--exemplified also by the struggle for religious freedom (thus, need for toleration)--becomes the model for *pluralism* (which requires no cosmopolitan concept of multiculturalism, rather a more realistic---evolutionarily speaking--multipolitanism of cultural hybridity, whose ever-evolving emergent characteristics turn the real pluralism of *concepts* of cosmopoly into just another feature of evolving hybridization). The keynote to seeing the importance of the basic human interest in the evolution of EuroAmerican culture--ergo it's derivative value of toleration--is to recognize the classical *humanistic* inspiration at the origin of Protestantism (arguments between Erasmus and Luther, before the tract on the door) which are aspects of Renaissance humanism. It is the humanistic ethos of evolving Christianity which compelled toleration, from which the interest in democratic equality arose. In his genealogy, Habermas' moral sleight of hand, which conflates the difference between internalist ethical inspiration (humanism) and externalist moral duty (rule universalism), returns. "We find Spinoza defending the freedom of religious expression with a view to the principle of freedom of conscience, thought and expression, and thus on moral grounds" (4), but Spinoza's "moral" grounds were distinctly virtue-ethical or internalist, in the spirit of a deepened individualistic interest in humanity, which argues for the importance of realized human potential, rather than catholic regulation. Supposedly "Locke opts for justification stemming from human rights," but his notion was not of human rights in the 20th century sense; Locke's natural rights of man entailed universalization of *education*, which became SO INTEGRAL to the spread of education in colonial America, long before talk of independent government (see _The Consent of the Governed: the Lockean legacy in early American culture_, Gillian Brown, Harvard UP, 2001)--which spoke to religious pluralism on Christian humanist grounds, from which the lower sense of mere toleration may be seen to derive in 17th century America. "Yet it was not until Pierre Bayle that we encounter stringently universalist reasons" (4). Who is Pierre Bayle? Sure: Looking for universalist reasons, one may encounter Pierre Bayle. But this further steers attention away from the humanistic basis of tolerance and a cultural, educational perspective toward outgrowing tolerance. Bayle was an impartialist-essentialist Calvinist skeptic who was probably a forerunner of modern skepticism than "the forerunner of Kant" (5), while "practices [of] mutual perspective-taking" obviously come from Christian notions of mutuality, which themselves arise from from Hellenistic ethics imported by the original Judeo-Christian sects. A keynote of Protestantism was a return to the pre-theocratic bases of the Christian experience, which depends on the ethical example of Christ, prior to doctrination as body of the church. Protestants expressed an the interest in direct empowerment by God through intimacy with Christ's example. Its comprehension of universalism is *ecumenical*, and the appeal of rationalistic universalism derives from that (and Stoic sources). So, Habermas has not yet, in his discussion, provided any basis for claiming that the basis of tolerance is rule-universalist, rather than deeply humanistic (therefore, no basis for steering attention away from educational opportunities for deeper humanism, as if justifiable coercion of equality is a preferrable way of thinking, rather than merely compensatory for educational underdevelopment). There is more than one way to "find a solution to the original paradox that prompted Goethe to reject toleration" (5). Political legalism without educational humanism has no choice but to regulatively enforce a sense of tolerance that is reasonable, since there's no basis in rule-universalism for seeing tolerance as a plateau in cultural evolution. But deepened humanism, born of "higher" education provides a basis for seeing beyond the necessity of cognitive dissonance. In particular, one person's (or one group's) problem with tolerance does NOT require universalistic enforcement of reciprocity (though I grant--beyond question--that universalism toward reciprocity is good and universality of reciprocity is ideal); rather, dissolving the problem only requires---relative to that person's / group's intolerance--that they become genuinely tolerant! This isn't a matter of mere compliance with the law, but rather of *really* being tolerant. EACH person's / group's problem with tolerance--their intolerance--requires individualized learning processes. No regime of "*universally convincing* delineation...[of] *reciprocally* take[n]...perspectives" can exist without relativity to the manifold idiosyncrasy of particular problems with tolerance. Universality of mutuality won't be accomplished by compliance with the law; justified coercion is just a holding pattern pending educational processes. So, we should conceptualize the problem of tolerance educationally in the first place. Rather than focusing on "rules of tolerant behavior" (5), I urge a focus on the *character* of tolerance. "Accordingly, the paradox is first resolved by the advent" of Renaissance, then Christian, humanism, rather than being *first* resolved "by the advent of modern democracy." "[T]he new secular source of legitimation" was humanist senses of freedom and self-determination, motivating interests in religious freedom, rather than "the universalistic meaning of reciprocal expectations" (5). Though I agree that universalist reciprocality is a virtuous perspective and a public good deserving of universal appreciation, it is not the case that religious toleration requires this. The parochialism that evokes calls (if not demands) for tolerance *has no access to the virtue of universality* prior to accomplishing specific tolerance relative to specific others. Such tolerance is *not* accomplished by internalizing universalism prior to appreciating the basic human interest that compels tolerance. Yet, it is the *humanism* latent to the basic human interest that provides the way to tolerance and for educationally overcoming the need for tolerance--a deepened, enriched humanism whose genealogy is Hellenistic and Christian humanist. The key to tolerance, as well as the way beyond tolerance, is *actual genuineness* toward the other, not normative conformance; in other words, it's a matter of internal reasons, rather than external reasons--a disclosable internal realism of the basic human interest (and its deeply humanistic background), rather than external realism of regulative prudence (which is useful, too, but not basically humanistic). Though obviously any "consensual delimitation can arise only through the mode of deliberation in which those involved are obliged to engage in mutual perspective-taking" (6), the problem of tolerance implies need for a mode of *reflection* in which those involved are *called upon* to engage in genuine understanding, which is based in progressive identification with the reflecting (mirroring and self-reflective) other, in which one's own humanity is enriched or deepened in the mutually formed "telos" of communicative understanding of *our* basic human interest. Robbed of that, we may be compelled to appeal to law; but what is preferrable deserves to be recognized, from a humanistic perspective that may also look universalistic (since it basically is: Hellenistic humanism is cosmopolitan, Christian humanism is ecumenical, and educational humanism is universalistic). So, though, "the [political] legitimating power of such deliberation is generalized and institutionalized only in the process of democratic will formation" (6), the *culturally* legitimating power of genuine communicative engagement is generalized and instututionalized only in processes of cultural education, which don't flourish best via justifiable coercion. "[A] deliberative process of legislation" may ensure tolerance, but it won't *cause* real education, and it won't provide a way beyond tolerance. I disagree that "religious toleration is basic to a democratic constitutional state" (6); rather *humanistic appreciation* of religious *freedom* is basic (in the U.S., at least--and humanism is superior to toleration). The meaning and existence of religious freedom is *entitled* constitutionally, but the basis of that freedom arises from the culture itself, as a discovery by constitutionality, not as a child of constitutionality. It is not *as* "religious community" that a group "must adopt the constitutional principle of the equal inclusion of everyone" (6); rather it is as *citizen* that one must *recognize* the freedom of the other. The imperative of inclusion belongs to the polis, not the religious community. One religious community may understand so little of another (whom it has to constructively live with) that it is necessarily compelled to reject the other's convictions, finding no basis at all for inclusion, relative to the religious community. But as citizens, the rejectors must substantively grant the other liberty and thus grant the other all due citizen entitlements. So, yes, "the liberal state expects...a cognitive adaptation to the ... secular community" (6), but a liberal *culture* hopes for more, and it is liberal culture that steers the liberal ship of state. Thus, tolerance should be understood as a minimalist derivative of educational humanism, not a necessary dissonance constrained by regulations. (In my view, law serves education, not the converse; philosophy of law *fosters* social evolution, beyond rule-universalism. I'm sure Habermas would approve this view, but is he furthering such a view or is he confounding it via apparent legalism?). [I must emphasize that, *as* a genuine Habermasian, I agree with most everything in an essay by him that I don't overtly disagree with; I'm in the process of working *with* his discourse, not against it. I see great potential for carrying on beyond his formulations, with deep respect for what he aims to do. That said, I will continue to disagree.] I disagree that "a religion that has become just one among several confessions must abandon this claim to comprehensively shape life" (6). Rather, such a religion must abandon a *political* aspiration to dominate, but its comprehensive claim upon its own community (internally a "reasonable" comprehensive doctrine) can be quite compatible with humanistic, even pluralist, appreciation of the necessary *mystery* of the other. There is an attainable intimacy of the mystery that can greatly deepen discernment of the basic human interest *within* religious experience, revealing a basis for interfaith humanism that is universalistic. There is abundant evidence for this in the humanitarian community. One might even argue that Habermas's generalizing sense of religion is itself parochial. In particular, he's quite wrong to claim (or adopt P. S-L's claim) that "missionary doctrines such as Christianity...are *intrinsically* intolerant of other beliefs" (7). Modern Catholicism looks very odd outside Europe *because* it assimilates local culture to take on an idiosyncratic local character. Such a tendency generally within Christianity (proven by the weird protestantisms in the rural U.S.) causes some scholars to argue that the future of Christianity is in the southern hemisphere. Anyway, religious tolerance "calls...for developing, from within the ethos of the religious community, cognitive links to" the ethical substance of humanistic society, which IS what Habermas calls "the moral substance of the democratic constitution" (7). The so-called "moral principles that govern co-existence in society as a whole" (8) are nothing other than the humanistic "ethical values" that *can be found* "held by a religious community" (8) that is living constructively in our modern world--non-fundamentalist Christianity, Judaism, and Islam; and Buddhism. The *fundamentalist* problem of tolerance is indeed a cognitive-ethical issue *within* religions themselves (as inauthentic apprehensions of the religion). The answer to low religion, within religion, is high religiosity---and the higher it goes, the more it looks like universalist humanism. But the universalistic potential of educational humanism is occluded by sociocentric thinking. Michael Aboulafia argues this quite specifically, in his critique of Habermas' reading of Mead, in Aboulafia's _The Cosmopolitan Self: George Herbert Mead and Continental Philosophy_, U. of Illinois Press, 2001. Habermas's sociocentric reading of Mead misses the creative, self-formative sense of Meadean identity, which Habermas reads as reflective autonomy (disembodying individuation in the body of socialization). Thus, individuation (we read over and over again) not only "occurs through socialization" (10), it looks like nothing else than a product of socialization, where a longing for integration eclipses the human interest in realizing one's potential, as if equality is an end in itself, rather than an ensurance for the sake of pluralistic freedom. O, sure, Habermas is a great advocate of pluralism, freedom, etc. But when you get to the textual details of basic argumentative claims, a different picture appears. "[L]inguistic and cultural traditions are...relevant for the formation and maintenance of the personal identity of individuals---something always interwoven with collective identities" (9-10). But what is the character (if not "nature") of the interweaving? "This insight has us opting for an intersubjectivist expansion of the abstract concept of the 'legal person'" (10). So, does this mean that interpersonal relations are the same as intersubjective relations? Is temporally "vertical" self identity (broadly and deeply "subjective") equivalent to communicatively "horizontal" personal identity? Is the depth of subjectivity humanistic in a potentially important sense that is *protected* by entitlement to privacy? In my experience, it's very important to distinguish the intersubjectivity of human life from the interpersonality of dialogal stances. Do we need an interpersonalist expanision of the abstract concept of legal person, or do we need a humanistic expansion: society geared toward the well-being of constructive freedom, True individuation, which is invisible to socialization? Individuation is a surprise to sociality, as more individuation yields more individuality, not more sociality--or rather, individuation yields (relative to sociality) an enriched sociality *derivative* of individuality which *advances* the character of sociality, even exemplarily (which the uniqueness of Habermas greatly demonstrates). But Habermas says---in passing, to be sure--- "persons...acquire and consolidate their identity" (10), but individuation is *not* something acquired; it's *accomplished*, and resultant identity remains *fluid*, even as "consolidated," since that consolidation is not a *structure* of self understanding, it's a *way* of going about one's "career" (in a broadly anthropological sense; cf. _The Human Career_, Walter Goldschmidt, Blackwell, 1990). Though "persons...articulate their understanding of themselves," the linguistic piecemealness of this is derivative of the lifespan-oriented holism that one is, an enactive "articulation" that is none other than that orientational "consolidation" that is one's way of life. But Habermas would reduce this to the dialogal stance (internalized as self-articulation). So, it's not *also* that a person will "develop their own life plan" distinct from understanding themselves or consolidating their identity. Rather, all three aspects happen together in self formation, only analytically distinguishable as identity, articulation and plan. So, *basically* the formation is neverending! Individuation's consolidating, enowning planful life goes on and on in its *singular* way, for any productive life. For the problem of religious tolerance, the *appeal* of enriched identity-articulation-career provides an entrance into enriched discernment of the basic human interest which religious experience can deepen (heighten) toward its destiny of disclosing the humanistic nature of its own capacity for appreciation. Here dwells "the internal ethos of the morality of human rights" (10). "A pluralistic society" is based on humanistic culture, which in turn grounds "a democratic constitution," but such a "constitution guarantees cultural differentiation only under the condition of political" freedom, rather than the derivative value of "the condition of political integration" (10). "The citizens of such a society are" *granted the freedom* to form or maintain their cultural idiosyncrasy, not "empowered" (10) to do so, since that empowerment arises from the culture itself, not from political constitutionality. "Such cultural empowerment is constrained by the" *responsibilities native to humanistic culture* that in turn warrants constitutional ensurances of cultural rights (otherwise, how could there be constitutional revision?); i.e., the constraint is vested in humanistic culture, only *derivatively* in the revisable "constitution that provides the justifications for cultural rights" (11). So, there may be an important sense in which the pluralism of worldviews and the pluralism of ways of life are kindred at heart, in ways of worldmaking and potentially ever-individuating views of one's progressing life. It may NOT be so important that one can divide one from the other, i.e., that "the civic virtue of toleration is challenged by the pluralism of *world views* in a different way than it is by the pluralism of *ways of life*" (11). Habermas occludes an important difference between authenticity and genuineness, when he evidently uses the terms interchangeably. The self interest in authenticity is not the same as the personal interest in genuineness. Minorities may *genuinely* "co-exist with equal rights," but it's inappropriate to say that they "would authentically" (11) do so. Minorities might authentically care to understand each other, and *thereby* genuinely co-exist. But then, "[m]ust we not assume that even then the cognitive dissonances would by no means disappear without a trace?" Well, we can't *assume* this, given the contrary perspective toward Habermas' approach to the issue that I've outlined above. We might even *expect* that the conditions of authentic care and the appeal of humanistic reflection may dissolve cognitive dissonance, perhaps in perspectives of religious humanitarianism that place starkly different cultural backgrounds in a shared evolution as, say, God's still-unfolding Creation that needs human diversity for evolution's fulfillment (though one might want to postpone showing how taking such a view to heart eventually dissolves religious experience into a deeply humanistic sense of the inherent *openness* of our evolutionary "telos"). Anyway, instead of "neutraliz[ing] the practical impact of a cognitive dissonance *that nevertheless in its own domain demands that we resolve it*" (12), we might learn how to give ourselves over to the cognitive dissonance as religious mystery, finding in its own domain *appeals* of majestically humanistic experience beyond one. Thanks for your time, Gary --- from list habermas-AT-lists.village.virginia.edu ---
Display software: ArchTracker © Malgosia Askanas, 2000-2005