Date: Sun, 26 Jan 2003 19:51:54 -0800 (PST) Subject: HAB: Integrating Philosophy & Everyday Life Ralph, I can admire, in your essay on your sense of "How to integrate philosophy and everyday life" (http://www.autodidactproject.org/my/phillife.html), that you want to clarify "what kind of work should be treated as legitimately philosophical in our time." I *"can"* admire this because you make clear in your essay that you want reliable resourcefulness for your thinking, rather than to emulate your "bureaucrat" who autonomously evaluates what "should be treated as legitimately philosophical." Neither you (I suppose) nor I (let me tell you) admire elitist thinking. But what IS "our time" such that philosophy is legitimate? What makes philosophy "legitimate in our time"? Your answer is, more or less, your sense of what's Hegelian—or, as you say in the end, "[t]he conception of philosophy [that is]...the full, self-confident unfolding of the powers of the human intellect, described by Fichte and Hegel." One could call this the self-formative interest. Indeed, your "autodidact"ical interest seems quite amenable to being called a self-formative interest. Habermas shows his appreciation of Hegel's interest as being self-formative in Habermas' early-'60s essay on Hegel's Jena lectures, in _Theory and Practice_; and this appreciation of Hegel is evident in Habermas' critique of Hegel's "philosophy of absolute reflection," in the early chapters of _Knowledge and Human Interest_ (which is also definitively critical of Marx's materialist reductionism, i.e., "the program for an instrumentalist translation of Hegel's philosophy of absolute reflection"; see http://www.marxists.org/reference/subject/philosophy/works/ge/habermas.htm). Anyway, the validity of the self-formative interest survives a critique of Hegelian absolutism. There is abundant reason to pursue the theme of the self-formative interest, both via Habermas's work and otherwise. My conviction of this has been a keynote of my participation with HAB List subscribers that past 5+ years, a theme which was also a keynote of my dissertation on Habermas, "The Discourse of Emancipatory Practice in Habermas's Historical Materialism" (1979) and in extended conversation with Habermas about parts of that dissertation, 1980. The interest in "a higher stage of formalization...and abstractness" is, of course, typical of the history of philosophy, just as the interest in "the art of philosophical thinking [as] the mediation of the abstract and the concrete"---mediating "the development of the capacity to think" and "a fine-tuned intuitive sense"---is typical of philosophical teaching, classically in the tutorial and commonly in the college classroom. I recall in high school---I've wanted to share this little story for a long time—my fascination with the debate club, the *form* of it, i.e., that each team had to be prepared to argue *either* side of the issue, when they went into competition. "The issue" for that year (shared among teams around the region) was always *genuinely* controversial, such that good arguments could be made for either side, and the prize went to the best team's argumentation. The amazing thing about the best teams was their ability to win in argumentation of either side! We see a similar "condition" of validity claims (as my little story continues) in jurisprudence, especially at the developmental stage of moot court, where law students may have to argue either side of a case. And questions from the bench have the function of clarifying what either party is exactly arguing (which we see in realworld law via appellate court events). Philosophical teaching can look a lot like questions from the bench (thinking of the tutorial, rather than the classroom). But philosophical teaching isn't *largely* or *basically* analogous to the juridical stance of impartiality (prior to judgment), since teaching---at its ideal "point" of tutorial---is interested in developing the thinking, not just, so to speak, doing archaeology (e.g., the early parts of a psychoanalysis); and teaching has no interest in definitive judgment, unlike the court. One good way to develop thinking is to find the point of apparently irresolvable controversy (relative to the other's apparent stage of conceptual understanding), working on the one hand to patiently distinguish what's apparently latent from what's really latent in the other's thinking; and on the other hand (in light of that) to clarify a (the?) relatively real irresolvability (relative to the other's determined "place" of reflection). Such working-through via working with the other may mean that the teacher takes on an argumentational stance *relative* to the other (rather than expressing his own view). This dynamic can be pursued further. Presently, I just want to suggest a direction for understanding "mediation" in "the art of philosophical thinking." I agree with you that "[p]hilosophy is a mode of cognition"---in part a reflective mode, but also an *historized* mode of cognition---"and its skills are conceptual." By 'historized', I want to mean (for the present) that good philosophy appreciates that the best of good philosophy is exemplified by the exemplary positions in philosophy, which constitutes its history—associated with the names of the philosophers exemplifying those milestone positions---not that anyone ever masters most of the best positions (though doctoral students are supposed to). But one's own development is more or less fated to more or less exemplify one of the exemplars, at best, such that one's development would be radically advanced by becoming a student of the exemplar (rather than pretending that philosophy begins with one's own wonder--while it really *does*, in a sense; see the work of Matthew Lipman and his Philosophy for Children movement). Plato "lives" because every Western teenager is likely at heart a Platonist, before entering into the pathway of developmental thinking called philosophy. A professional philosopher might genuinely believe s/he's far beyond, say, Plato (as, say, an Analytical philosopher, i.e., a practitioner of inquiries in the 20th century Analytical tradition) only to be one day exposed as a closet Platonist. How this happens is that, in one's way through the history of philosophy, one meets Plato relative to one's own self-formative interest (and its stage of conceptual self-formation) that affords a *representation* of what Plato thinks, which justifies (through critique or critical appreciation of "Plato") a passage of thinking beyond "Plato" which turns out to have been basically a genuine passage of one's development beyond that *representation* of Plato, which remained nonconsciously Platonic at heart. So, indeed, one comes to hope that, as you say, "[c]onscious philosophy enables a person to penetrate beneath phenomenal appearances and ideological smokescreens to uncover the underlying essence of any phenomenon or picture of reality," but it turns out that searching for "the...essence" of the "picture" perpetuates a reflection of the searcher whose searching is thereby destined to remain basically "conscious" in that sense, i.e., as a searching for some essence of itself searching. Of *course* we want to frame the phenomenality of appearances so as to understand them fundamentally. But what that fundamentality IS has been understood in other ways than as an essence (the fundamentality of searching may outgrow essentialism). To say that philosophy "is a quest for insight into objective reality beyond appearance" is just to declare a stance that *conceals* other modes of reality. Habermas, you may know (having endured subscription to the HAB list for some time, you noted last March), distinguishes objective reality from its intersubjectivity and subjectivity, as does Hegel (though JH makes the distinctions on a different basis: *cognitive-linguistic* differentiations of world relations, based in "formal pragmatics"), so your objectivist stance isn't yet nearing Hegel's, though you seem to idealize absolute reflection. You ask: "Does the highest stage of self-consciousness...require total embodiment in[] systematic abstract reflective thought?" No. There is no highest stage of self-consciousness. But one can understand the search for the highest stage highly, i.e., well. There, the fundamentality of conceptualization evolves (but to say this surely doesn't make sense as a mere assertion). Meanwhile, the history of philosophy has progressed through—thus evolved—fundamentalities, what Heidegger calls "stemmings" in "the history of Being," which culminate in the 20th century phenomenological/deconstructive critique of metaphysicalism (i.e., in a phrase, the aspiration to disclose the essence of highness), which gave Europe the mandarin Kantian intellectual culture of post-WWI Germany (cf. _The Genesis of Heidegger's *Being and Time*_, Theodore Kisiel, 1993) which turned into Zarathustrian support for Nazism (cf. _The Heidelberg Myth_, Steven P. Remy, Harvard UP 2003), whose essence (having sought essence) was, according to Heidegger (in his Nietzsche lectures of the 1940s), "the spirit of revenge." But that's the extreme. The domestication of this shows in the romance of The Concept, longing for some awe-inspiring integration of abstraction that then patronizes the common folk in terms of its charitable vision of the heights, as it mediates its achievement with the people--which tends toward so-called (by deconstructionists) "logocentrism". For example, to believe, as you say, that "for me the heart of philosophy consists of ontology, epistemology, and logic" accords with logocentrism in philosophy, as does an attitude toward ethics as "possible laundry list[] of concrete assertions about this and that" (i.e., ethics is a lowly derived mode of systematics). But I agree with you that "the development of abstract reflection and deep intuition are both indispensable," yet the evolution of thinking indicates that the "and" of reflection and intuition is, fundamentally, beyond systematics. Or so I would argue. I could emphatically agree with you that "[n]ot only can philosophy [without quote marks - G] illuminate everyday life, but everyday life and social practice may supply...nourishment" for reflection. But dailiness is not sufficient, of course; so I can't agree that it may supply "the nourishment and discipline" for reflection, nor can I subscribe to a notion of reflection which is basically "abstract reflection." It is dangerous, after the 20th century, to presume to refer substantively to "the formal philosophical heritage of the human race," since aspiration "to develop one's capacities" belongs to all, whatever their conditions of life. This was the key point of Noble Laureate Economist Amartya Sen in _Development as Freedom_, 1999, as well as some approaches to the aims of education (which focus on actualization of human potential; see _Of Human Potential_, Israel Scheffler, 1980? Also: _Extraordinary Minds_, Howard Gardner, 1999?). Also, Ralph, the spirit of revenge is obvious in your relations to others. Though you write that "I do not seek to...devalue...the capacity of various people to think," this claim is starkly undermined by your communicative practice. Yet it's true that "the inept application of abstract thought just creates more confusion and static," but "all the bad philosophy that surrounds us" reflects your overt contempt for what doesn't reflect your aspiration to be a German Idealist, and there's no need to be contemptuous of other's lack of interest in 19th century idealism. It's just so unfortunate that you "have not found one book in my lifetime of any use in teaching the art of philosophical thinking as I envision it." Clearly, the notion of envisioning should not be beyond question. So, the emancipatory interest of knowledge—so integral to Habermas's _Knowledge and Human Interest_—should not be overlooked, for philosophy is not only a means of enlightenment, but also (as Wittgenstein famously advocated, and the Ordinary Language school of analytical philosophy advanced) philosophy can also be therapeutic--maybe even in a *psycho*therapeutic sense. For example, anyone who has a grandiose sense of self-importance AND believes that he or she is "special" and unique and can only be understood by, or should associate with, other special people AND is interpersonally exploitative, i.e., takes advantage of others to achieve his or her own ends AND lacks empathy: is unwilling to recognize or identify with the feelings and needs of others AND shows arrogant, haughty behaviors or attitudes, THEN that person exhibits five of the nine traits of narcissistic personality disorder required for that diagnosis (http://www.psychologynet.org/npd.html). From a philosophical perspective (the interest in the conceptuality of one's self-formative interest), one might be concerned about the intellectualizing of someone with that disorder, e.g., the conceptual *crudeness* of one's contempt for others who don't satisfy one's needs, as exhibited by a moderately-toned writing that suddenly turns nasty whenever it refers to others, as you do in your postings, and as you do at points in your essay under discussion. Habermas' explicates the emancipatory interest philosophically, as a critique of Nietzsche in Freud, who developed the emancipatory interest in his discovery of psychotherapy (albeit as very long-term psychoanalysis). Nietzsche, of course, had an epochal sense of narcissism, in his Zarathustrian longing. You *have* read some Habermas, haven't you? ------------------------------------------------------------------------ Anyway, if you're still reading---or to others, at least--let me say that I use postings to try out stances, as well as to occasionally assert my own position on things (rarely; and even then too spontaneously, I later realize). Sometimes, I have the apparently silly notion (given lack of response) that thinking "aloud" will be useful to others, even causing constructive discussion. In short, I'm not posting for self-expressive reasons--almost never. Even my extended defenses of Habermasian thought over the past 5+ years began as an overt effort to *appropriate* Habermasian stances to come-what-may on the list, rather than to basically express my own stance toward Habermas's thinking (which is eclectic, in the flow of other kinds of developments). In short, I haven't been in a struggle for recognition, rather an experiment in online discourse. That means that my postings are usually *stances*, often in the spirit of a debating club (but there's nothing ingenuous or cynical about this; it's just a matter of living *mediation*). One may suspect I'm a conservative (a frivolous mistake) because I'm interested in what the rationality of the Bush administration might be, but actually I'm just practicing the hermeneutics of understanding rather spontaneously. Generally, it's so much more interesting to base critique (to which I haven't given time, relative to the Bush administration) on understanding of the other rather than caricature. Slamming caricatures is just too easy. As every psychotherapist knows, even misfits embody a claim to rationality (while no decent psychotherapist would regard a client simply as a misfit, I should add); and every psychotherapist knows that the *efficacy* of therapeutic action happens only within the "rationality" of the other. Of course, I don't have any chance of changing any conservative minds, but a first stage in such a process must be to understand conservative thinking *from the conservative perspective*. But my interest in this has been slight (as shown in my loss of interest in the Bush administration rejection of the Kyoto process). Anyway, critique that has any realistic hope of emancipatory efficacy, e.g, turning, say, "Conservative" support for an issue into "Liberal" support of *practical* alternatives (rather than just preaching to the "radical" choir in oppositional caricatures that organize the tribe against power, but without a clue about how progressive alternatives might go)--and / or to *practically* translate Liberal understanding into genuinely progressive alternatives, when that's appropriate--such critique must begin from a stance of understanding the "rationality" of the other's *own* perspective. Now, radicals have always been too important for such tedious work; after all, it's about organizing against power rather than learning how to work it to progressive ends. But when I *do* generally work this way--the labels fall away. What remains salient is, so to speak, the hybridity of the things themselves: the lifeworld conditions that engage the *whole mix* of folks (especially as the scale of consideration increases, from locality to region), the organizational conditions, the administrative conditions, etc., each of which involve all age levels and backgrounds of understanding (which any successful politician grasps intimately), such that *genuinely* understanding any important issue is, to be fair to it, a very, very elusive thing. (I know this from years of trench-level experience with "educational reform" at several levels of "trench.") *Consensus*-based progressivity is a very difficult thing, but no broadly appealing political program is possible without it. -------------------------------------------------------------- Jumping contexts, I wonder sometimes that perhaps Habermas's philosophy is well-suited for theory of diplomacy. But thinking about this requires a real understanding of the conditions of effective diplomacy amidst the realities of international relations, which seems much like a small town writ large (a town with inestimable ethnic diversity---like Berkeley, where I've lived for over a quarter century, not that I think of the daily planet as Berkeley, though a local free newspaper named The Daily Planet recently died from lack of advertising. Let me tell you that a luxury of free media has a natural-selective dynamic to it). In the global village, its a vanity fair, with the threats of punks in the night, progressive programs that can't survive the passing on of their originators (Will the UN dissolve into the community of alliances as one "regionalism" among more territorial ones?), litigations for remedy whose cost bankrupts the best of intentions ("No good intention goes unpunished" is a legacy in activist Berkeley, as well as with UN agencies), too few local specialists for the labyrinth of special problems (steep slopes in the sojourn of regional educational opportunity; and the foreign students in the U.S. choose to stay), etc., etc. At the level of an actual town, one can make sense of the prospects and challenges of leadership, and one might hope that social theory and practice contributes to the formation and sustainability of progressive, realistic groups that have leading effects across electoral eras. It's pragmatic to wonder the extent to which learning from local progress can inform understanding of international relations---working from "Think globally, Act locally" to thinking about what is *really* involved in the "locality" of acting globally. The 24-hour news cycle is a global locality. The issue of "Iraq" has been a great example of how global communications have enforced a learning curve on Texas conservatism. It has dimensions such as that European undermining of the diplomatic threat of force against Iraq undermines Colin Powell's diplomatic position relative to Donald Rumsfeld's military position in the interpretation of "Iraq" by Bush's inner circle of advisors. Like in 2000, when a vote for Nader was effectively a vote for Bush, going "French" is a feather in the cap of unilateral militarism. The global locality works this way. Vanity fair, gangs, bright minds vs dim minds, reliable institutions of diplomacy vs political adventurisms of every stripe. Daily planet...small world...six degrees of separation in the netweave of social evolution. Yet, any short depiction of anything important looks either facile or obscure. So, my point here, I guess, is that thinking works by analogy as much as anything, such that discourse—a means of discovery, prior to being a means of justification--faces issues of modeling prior to issues of validation. Conceptualizing the issues in a problem complex is a primary purpose of what is called "theory" in the humanities (and I would understand the human sciences with emphasis on the "human"), and discourse about conceptualization seems to me a primary purpose of philosophy. So a path from lifeworld to philosophy goes through the range of levels and kinds of conceptual modeling by which we render our understandings and, conversely, by which philosophy appropriates itself to life. Habermas is perhaps the best example of this kind of work for me, as he has mastered so many idioms. Well, I'm stopping here arbitrarily. Best regards to all (especially Ralph), Gary --- from list habermas-AT-lists.village.virginia.edu ---
Display software: ArchTracker © Malgosia Askanas, 2000-2005