Date: Tue, 2 Sep 2003 16:07:21 -0700 (PDT) Subject: [HAB:] success vs. aim; meaning vs. rationality; act vs. scene re: Antti, "Re: Commissive vs. perlocutionary speech" Antti, Yes, I believe I know what you mean. A> ...[perlocutionary act is] not a term in mainstream speech act theory as known by non-Habermasians. > Take illocutionary success, one bone of contention between Habermas and Searle. Suppose I say to you "The New Jersey Devils won 5-1 last night" in order to inform you of this fact. For Searle, illocutionary success would be a matter of convention and context; if they are in order, I have managed to inform you, in other words, performed an act with the intended illocutionary force. The question is simply: what kind of act did I perform in/by saying these words? G: a constative speech act? A> But for Habermas, illocutionary success consists in intersubjective recognition of validity claims (because that is what the "illocutionary aim" of a speech act is, according to him). G: I disagree, though I believe I appreciate your point that there may be evidence that Searle has a credible accusation against JH (though, I would argue, not a valid one). I believe that JH has a different view from what you represent. In any case, I disagree that illocutionary success "consists in" etc. It seems to me that such-and-such, which I'll indicate in a moment. Because I presume that JH has more insight into these matters than I, I infer that, if I'm correct in my such-and-such disagreement, JH would agree. This attitude has served me well in the past, as I've discovered that I do indeed think in a Habermasian manner (not to be self-serving, but I don't have textual documentation for my following disagreement). We should take to heart the difference between communicative action and specific speech acts that scenes of communicative interaction contain. A speech act is usually *nested* in communicative action, not only serially (multiple speech acts make a sum total of a scene or period of interaction) but as means toward actualizing guiding intents or points (speech acts are subordinate to other acts, in the rhetoric, if not logic, of making a point). Illocutionary aim can be ideal-typically located in particular speech acts, but this is ordinarily derivative of communicative aim (scenic aim) which belongs to the communicative action which component acts serve. Illocutionary success, on the other hand, pertains more to specific speech acts than to the scene. So, I believe that JH would agree to a distinction between illocutionary success and aim, though a speech act can be analytically construed apart from scenes, as if communicative action is a single speech act. Ideal-typically, communicative action is *like* its model-theoretic exemplar: the speech act. I would also distinguish--and believe that JH does, too--illocutionary aim from the rationality of the aim. When we do things with words, we seek to convey something for understanding or appreciation. We are not normally in the mode of *justifying* what we convey, and logically can't do so simultaneously with the conveyance of understanding. Speech acts imply a validity basis, but we don't normally talk in order to be seen as justified (We comfortably may presume this between each other, except in scenes intended to address the questionability of this). To do otherwise is normally considered defensive or expressive of some communicative problem. Unproblematic communication is not always in the mode of insecurity or risk of baselessness. So, the real difference between specific acts and the scene of activity is indicated in a distinction between success and aim. The real difference between non-problematic and problematic communication is indicated in a distinction between action and the implied rationality of that action. A> Intuitively, I can inform you of something even if you do not accept what I say as true. G: Can you? Ken MacKendrick a couple of days ago asserted a citation as backing for a point he made, but the citation didn't exist. Was I informed of anything by his assertion until I questioned it? Or was I just not informed of anything at all? (Presumably, Ken believed that what he asserted was true.) It's more than plausible that: A>... It is, of course, still plausible that I have *successfully* informed you only if you come to believe what I said, and this is the intuition that Habermas seems to be following. G: Indeed, you can use information in a false assertion and unwittingly, genuinely intend that I consider myself informed via that assertion, but succeeding with an informational speech act can serve several larger contexts of communicative action, including I be informed, but also perhaps that I recognize that you believe that such-and-such (rather than something else), or even that you are self-deceptively manipulating me (if not maliciously doing so, i.e., with conscious intent. But *I*'m not paranoid---as this story goes---rather I just don't believe what you say, and have no idea whether you believe it, too). So, if you assert something for the sake of informing me, and I do not accept what you say as true, your illocutionary success (I understand what you're saying) is not accomplishing your illocutionary aim! A> If you don't believe me and get into trouble, I can later say "You have nothing to complain about, you were informed". G: Someone acting in an official capacity would say that. But that presumes that what you say is reliable *because* you are participating in a duly authorized scene of fair warning or some such. *Normally*, if I get into trouble because I didn't believe you, I can indeed complain that I had good reason for not regarding your statement as true, if not complaining that there was good reason to not regard you as reliable, and that you're culpable for that (though, before being harmed, I would just let your unreliability go uncontested). In short, speech acts normally participate in scenes of communicative action. Success serves an aim; the two are not the same. A> In that case it is not constitutive of performing an illocutionary act that it achieves intersubjective recognition..... G: I'd say (claiming to speak for JH) that intersubjective recognition belongs to the understanding of meaning, rather to the implicature of validity bases. Though indeed, to know the meaning of a speech act includes knowing what its implied validity basis is, the tacitity of the latter (in fluid interaction) is distinct from the explicitity of the former. Knowing the validity basis of your assertion doesn't mean that I'm constantly questioning everything you say (or if it does, *you're* the one in trouble). So, it IS "constitutive of performing an illocutionary act that it achieves intersubjective recognition," but *not* constitutive that the act is received as questionable. A> [For] Habermas .... It is not enough that you come to believe what I said,.... G: There's a difference between understanding what you say and believing it. Meaning is not the same as truth-functionality. "I know what you mean, but I haven't decided whether or not I believe it. After all, I DO know I've never been abducted by extraterrestrials, but I love your story!" However, if I come to believe it, this will be because I.... A> ... recognize the validity claims inherent in my utterance. G: So, let me use *your* words now, to say (with my own meaning of 'this') that: A> In something like this manner, communicative rationality is immanent in illocutionary aims. So, for different reasons, I fully agree with you that: A> ...[I]n going beyond the modest constitutive analysis offered by traditional speech act theory, Habermas also goes beyond mere conceptual analysis and adds substantive normative content into the concepts. A> [I have] sketched three possible senses of "illocutionary success": performing a speech act with the intended illocutionary force, ... G: Note that illocutionary force is an analytical notion. When I talk, I'm not per se performing a speech act; I'm telling you something. Analytically, my speaking can be classified as a speech act with at least two illocutionary components: a performative intent that has a specifiable force. But it's not unfair to your first sense to just say that there are speech acts. We don't intend illocutionary force apart from the performance. A> ...[2] inducing the corresponding perlocutionary effect in the hearer, G: If this is a second possibility, then it's more than just any speech act, since all speech acts have a perlocutionary component. "Inducing" an effect requires that you regard your given speech act as serving a communicative intent to get a specific effect. Here the speech act is a means within a tactical communicative action. A> ...and [3] getting the hearer accept the validity claims raised. G: To do that, you must have a second speech at as the propositional content of your current one. So here, the given speech act serves a communicative scene of justification. Your three possibilities here are: ordinary communicative action (oriented toward understanding), instrumental action, and justification. A> Habermas needs the third of these to show that communicative rationality is part and parcel of language use, but what can he say to an opponent who insist on the first or second alternative? G: He would say, more or less, that a tacit claim to justifiability is implied by ordinary conveyance, and knowing what you mean implies that I have an available sense of what the validity basis of your meaning is. My acceptance of what you say (in your unreflective flow of conversation) may be unrelated to your sense of justifiability, but that usually doesn't matter. I'm a therapist (let's say), and you're a UFO group member, and we can talk about this just fine without worrying right now about our background views on the matter. Believe me, I *understand* (I think---or if I'm wrong, we're both in trouble. Or else: Beam me up!). G>>I see no reason not to admit [perlocutionary] acts into speech act theory and thus to give them a name perlocutions or perlocutionary speech acts. A> It is possible, but also possibly very misleading, since Austin (and others following him) use "perlocution" for the act of persuading or convincing someone or getting someone to do something by saying something. G: But the "act" of persuading isn't done with single speech acts. It takes a communicative scene. What's misleading is *not* the inclusion of perlocutionary speech into theory, but the confinement of communicative action theory to the ideal-typical speech act---in short: pragmatics without rhetoric. I told Habermas in 1980 that rhetoric belongs to what he's doing, along with pragmatics in his theory of language. Communicative action cannot be fairly theorized within pragmatics. It requires a rhetorical focus. He agreed. And you see in _Theory of Communicative Action_ (not by my doing, surely) that a theory of argument is distinguished from other features of the theory. Austin would be the first to lament the decline of rhetoric in the university, and I'm pleased to see the re-ascendence of this discursive formation (which seems to have plateaued in the U.S.). --------------------------- You say that: A> ...[I]n... 'Some Further Clarifications of the Concept of Communicative Rationality'... he speaks of "perlocutions" as [something that] cannot be rationally disputed.... G: But you then contradict yourself, apparently: A> His example is "You act like a pig!" - to be sure, you can dispute it ("No, I don't!"), but that is beside the point. G: To my blind date, this would not be beside the point, not to mention to the point of my indignity. So, yes indeed, the insult can be disputed or, as JH writes (via English---he corrects translations before they're published, by the way) "challenged" (331). The communicative action which employs the insult can be challenged re: "the lack of truthfulness of the declaration of intention [presuming you didn't want to be insulting, just rib me jealously, because my blind date is a babe] and the lack of truth of the existential presupposition" (ibid.), presuming I have no sense of humor or you're mentally retarded and need to know what a pig is (JH is actually addressing another perlocution at this quoted point, but this applies to the "swine" statement, too). The illocutionary components of the perlocution can be "negated", as well as "the context presupposed by the speaker." I would add that normally, perlocutions don't occur without contexts of action, such that the instrumentality of intent implies a truth-functional claim that there is a specifiable success intended, and one can dispute that such a success is likely to occur (or even demonstrate that it won't occur), which point JH makes, i.e., instrumental actions necessary implicate themselves in contexts that carry validity claims. There are normally no instrumental actions that don't imply a background context that depends on validity claims. "In such a case," JH writes (if I may piggyback on his interest in swindle), " the [perlocutionary] speech act is not strictly speaking *contested*; rather it is simply explained why the intended effect will not occur...." Now we get to the statement that you provide as evidence (in German) that: A> "perlocutions" do not, according to [JH], raise validity claims,.... JH> Only illocutionary acts that can be *valid* or *invalid* can be contested" (ibid.). G: Yet, the point he has been making up to this point is that perlocutions have illocutionary components. Moreover, his attention to context accords with my distinction between the speech act and its scene of communicative action (a point I made above before I looked up your quote). So, there is validity implicature inside and outside the perlocution. One can validly say that perlocutions are presumably rational and can be disputed because they're parasitic on communicative action. It is not the case that: A> This sort of speech act in a way openly flouts the demands of justifiability or appropriateness; they wear, as it were, their invalidity on their sleeves. G: On the contrary, perlocutionary action may be justifiable and appropriate. Didactic, directive, and instructional activity is often justifiable, because it implies and is comprised by illocutionary activity and aspects. Yet, you're clearly correct that A> They [i.e., illocutionary and perlocutionary acts] simply have a different role in language. G: Nonetheless: G> > All speech acts participate in the validity basis of speech. [...] --- from list habermas-AT-lists.village.virginia.edu ---
Display software: ArchTracker © Malgosia Askanas, 2000-2005