Date: Fri, 3 Oct 2003 23:32:53 -0700 (PDT) Subject: [HAB:] Endnote on pragmatics of justification At the bottom of page 371 (_OPC_), Habermas wants to show how all the pieces of his case may accord as a singular argumentation sketch. Again, JH is providing a pragmatic theory of justification (and application), not a pragmatic theory of truth (though a pragmatic theory of truth can be derived from my modified version of his argumentation, which I would call an *appropriative* theory of truth). So: JH: ...we have only to bring together in the right way the partial statements assembled here up to now. [First,] In the lifeworld actors depend on behavioral certainties. G: You recall that I focused on this earlier, but I want to add a new dimension to JH's assertion here. By "actor," JH means, of course, a person or participant in activity or carrying through action. But JH's theory of action types (TCA-1) includes dramaturgical action, such that we are always, to some degree, actors in self-representation of our lives (subjectivities, according to JH, but I will give richer meaning to dramaturgical action than does JH--not today--in full accord with what JH means by dramaturgical). The pragmatic importance of this presently is that the actor is primarily understood relative to action---persons as action-interested and action-oriented. Persons' relationships to knowledge and understanding, with wide variations of certainty (and uncertainty), pertain to all types of action. "Behavioral" certainties are not the keynote of lifeworld relations to knowledge and representational understanding. But a sense of bedrock behavioral certainty is what JH needs for his theory to associate to some "unconditional" feature, in the following synoptic statement: JH: There is a *practical* necessity to rely intuitively on what is unconditionally held-to-be-true. This mode of unconditionally holding-to-be-true is reflected on the discursive level in the connotations of truth claims that point beyond the given context of justification and require the supposition of ideal justificatory conditions---with a resulting decentering of the justification community. (372) G: JH claims that he's "bringing together partial statements," but he hasn't earlier claimed that "there is a practical necessity to rely intuitively on what is unconditionally held-to-be-true," unless one reads his earlier reference to behavioral certainties as meaning just that. But JH has simply *presumed* the place of behavioral certainties earlier, and I've earlier indicated how (1) there are levels and gradations of lifeworld background, contrary to his apparently monolithic regard for the lifeworld backgroud; and (2) we normally live with degrees of certainty about the objective world (JH also presumes a singular relevance of the objective world, which is contrary to the fluidity of the lifeworld itself; his own argumentation about "truth", "rationality", and "justification" moves around types of validity claims, but he thematizes the lifeworld-to-discourse twofold relative to only the objective domain of the lifeworld). There is no argumentative basis--nor, to my mind, plausibility--to treating the lifeworld background as a general bedrock of presumptive unconditionality (with clear prevalence of the objective world's relevance). Therefore, there could be no valid correlate "reflected on the discursive level" that suggests any salient unconditionality for truth claims. Moreover, the only way to justify a focus on bedrock thinking in the lifeworld is to emphasize pre-conventional and concrete-operational consciousness, which is associated with children and illiteracy. So, the more that one incorporates a lifeworld of educated adults and advanced modernization, the less that bedrock thinking figures into a general appreciation of the lifeworld---and the less credible is any correlate unconditionality for discursive "reflection". So, the more that one presumes immaturity and illiteracy, the more that a reflection of unconditionality is to be found at the discursive level, which would be something like a Platonism. But Platonism is *not* connoted by a pragmatic theory of justification that is modified in the way that I've suggested over the previous series of postings in light of JH's discussion. Overtones of a "required" unconditionality that look ultimately stipulated are of no significance for the basic tenability of a twofold hermeneutic, from lifeworld to discourse and back, i.e., an appropriative pragmatic of justification and application. There is no unconditionality required "on the discursive level in... connotations of truth claims that point beyond the given context of justification...." Of course, truth claims often do point beyond the given context of justification, but there are many degrees of scale short of unconditionality. A "supposition of ideal justificatory conditions" is desirable, but seldom "required" in any full dress degree. (Note that his earlier "presupposition" of ideal conditions has now become "supposition", as I recommended earlier). A "resulting decentering of the justification community," anticipated by that "point beyond the given context of justification" takes on a degree of scale that accords with the appropriate degree of "beyond" that is at point. I agree, though, that: JH: ...the process of justification can be guided by a notion of truth that *transcends justification*.... (372) G: But the "can" doesn't imply "must"; it's up to the participants to decide the degree of idealization that's appropriate. For example, survey researchers may desire that an ideal of scientific corroboration be anticipated by compelling results of antedotal information gathering, but the *degree* to which that idealization is feasible or realistic (given costs of rigor or difficulties coding for fluid variables) is one of the questions that inquirers may face, while the idealization of empirical certainty provides a tool for evaluating the degree of validity that available results justify. ------------------------------------ The remainder of Habermas' essay (372-77) continues his critique of Rorty, so his pragmatic of justification becomes largely critical application, and is worthwhile reading---critical exemplification---for that reason; but my interest is, has been, and remains the philosophical pragmatics as such, and JH doesn't return to this anymore in his essay, so it's time to move on to the next venue. Proper closure here would be to retrieve all the themes and modifications I've suggested over the past week and organize them into a coherent discursive summation. But I'll do that much later, with much more material, since I need to circulate through many other basic passages of Habermas' thinking, in order to clarify what I have in mind. Next: "world-disclosure" and the "roots of rationality" in "Some Further Clarifications of the Concept of Communicative Rationality," _OPC_, ch. 7. Gary --- from list habermas-AT-lists.village.virginia.edu ---
Display software: ArchTracker © Malgosia Askanas, 2000-2005