Date: Wed, 24 Mar 2004 06:03:05 -0500 Subject: [HAB:] GERMAN IDEALISM & THE JEW [3]: denouement Mack, Michael. German idealism and the Jew: the inner anti-semitism of philosophy and German Jewish responses. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 2003. I finally finished my quick first reading of this book. As a whole it proves to be a disappointment. At best it is a compendium of interesting data subject to expansion and conceptual evaluation, but as a coherent presentation, the book is a failure. It is important to examine how a specialized work of this sort can get away with this. If it were written for a general audience, presumably a fuller background exposition would be needed. Some background is assumed, or so it seems, and so the author can supply a certain amount of detail for the ideas he wants to examine. However, the gross generalizations, connections between thinkers, and systematic analysis of ideas do not hold up. The poverty of philosophy in understanding history is complemented by the poverty of history of ideas in examination of systems of concepts. I read the remaining chapters of Rosenzweig, Freud, Benjamin, and the conclusion, which treats two other figures, Elias Cannetti and someone named Steiner. There are two fundamental problems in this book, to begin with. The first is an assumption of commonality among various German thinkers and a lack of systematic examination of their ideas. Wagner for example may be an idealist in a generic sense but I see no evidence he represents a systematic development of the philosophical tradition known as German idealism. Idealism is used in a generic sense which may be appropriate for certain purposes but hardly covers in an adequate fashion a specific philosophical tradition. I will say more about this when we come to Freud. The second problem lies in the generalizations about the German-Jewish thinkers adduced in the book. Mack's characterization of both the Germans and German Jews is based on a single theme treated antithetically. But this hardly unifies either group or systematically compares one to the other. Secondly, Mack does not face the banality and/or obscurantism of many of the German-Jewish thinkers or analyze the basis of the distinctions among them. The problem with the latter group is the extent to which their philosophies (not just their sensibilities or outsider status) are based upon some re-metaphorized philosophical conception of Judaism to counter other philosophies or ideologies. A Benjamin, Freud, or Marx succeed to the extent to which they are universal thinkers, however their perspectives may have social roots in the marginalized experience of an outsider ethnic group. However, attempts to construct a Jewish countermythology to fight a prevailing mythology regress to unacceptable banality the more they depend on a specifically Jewish mythology and metaphysics. I find nothing remotely interesting about Rosenzweig, just as I have never been interested in Buber or Fackenheim or any others who attempt to construct a specifically Jewish philosophy. Such attempts are retrogressive in the modern world. They drag us back inside the world of ideology, reversing the decisive break Marx made with the Young Hegelians in the mid-1840s for their inability to think beyond the insides of ideology. I have the same problem here as I have with liberation theology of all ilks: as metaphor or poetry it may have some value, but as philosophy or a belief system it is all bullshit. Mythmaking, even the making of a countermyth, is a dangerously inadequate basis for understanding the modern world, and parochial, arbitrary and obscurantist in its application to the understanding of material circumstances. I would also include Michael Lerner's upper middle class liberal pabulum known as the "politics of meaning" in this category of ideological masturbation. Before I rise again to generalizations, I want to summarize the remaining chapters. Again my caveat: I did not take very good notes. Rosenzweig has an argument against Kantian autonomy: it abandons any meaningful relationship to the external world, and it is impossible to will in general. R also used the Kantian argument against Islam and accused Kant of being Islamic (heteronymous). R claims that epistemology usurps infinity (the unknown). The gap between immanence and transcendence is eliminated. The next chapter is on Rosenzweig vs. Hegel and the politics of blood. There is more on the interesting interaction of pseudotheology and pseudoscience (128). R argues that the superhuman Aryan body is essentially superphysical, i.e. not material at all but ideal. There is also a counterargument to something Hegel says about the metaphysics of eating. Schelling is not condemned as a reactionary but praised for asserting that the Jews are "chosen" because of their nonparticipation in the violent struggle between states. R is also a disturbingly "blood-and-soil" thinker. For him Jews are united by a blood brotherhood, and blood is outside of history. It is difficult to read this stuff without gagging. This drivel is hardly materialist. As a mythical conception it may have some interesting moments, not to mention nauseating ones, but it is mythmaking nonetheless, at its very worst. Freud's outlook should not be defined by his antireligious book THE FUTURE OF AN ILLUSION, according to Mack. Freud is very much a Jewish thinker. He sees anti-Semitism as an inner psychical reality dominating outer reality. Judaism engaged in conscious remembrance of past trauma. There is some stuff on the castration complex and Weininger's and Jung's denial of sexuality. Perhaps the most interesting topic in this chapter is Freud's repeated references to Kant's categorical imperative as essentially a form of taboo, a self-authorizing dogma equivalent to the superego (143-149). There is also an interesting discussion of MOSES AND MONOTHEISM. But the most important ideas I think are the Kantian categorical imperative and the denial of reality or neurotic amnesia. I'll get back to Freud's approach to philosophy later. Walter Benjamin links the evolution to Christianity to Kant and the metamorphosis of Christianity into capitalism, with a concomitant abstract devaluation of the empirical world. There is also something about baroque allegory. Finally, there is a concluding chapter, in which Mack introduces Cannetti and Steiner. Mack is writing this book out of a post-Holocaust perspective, and there me conclusions that can be drawn for postmodernism. Very disappointing. The overall theme, I gather, is the Jewish response to the idealist repression of materiality. While granting that this generic theme may be an important one, it is not adequate for organizing one's whole thinking about this range of thinkers. There are multiple reasons for this. Beyond what I've said before, I'll try to briefly explain the most important. The theme of "materiality", while an important one, should not obscure the fact that many of these thinkers who try to reinsert materiality to counter its denial or devaluation, are hardly materialist thinkers, but mythical thinkers. They may recognize an ideological opponent they can smoke out, but their own mythical constructs are grossly inadequate, even though they may serve as countermyths to contrary dubious ideological constructs. The problem here is in relying on Jewish countermyths to Christian, volkish, and statist myths. While the motives for doing so may be appealing, they work better in the genre of satire than they do in philosophy per se. The generic concept of idealism as a form of repression/denial may well be important, but it isolates one theme or one mechanism, and while imposing one aspect of systematicity organized around this single theme, bypasses the systematicity of the actual philosophical systems under discussion. And this is what a psychoanalytical approach also fails to address. Which brings me back to Freud as an example of explaining this problem. In focusing on symptomology, Freud overlooks systematicity. Freud bypasses ideology critique as traditionally conceived, which focuses on the systemic structure of concepts under criticism. But in supervening this level of analysis by seeking out psychological motives, the psychoanalyst effectively conjures the structure of the concepts themselves out of existence. When it comes to symptomatology, Nietzsche was far superior to Freud, because Nietzsche understood and analyzed the systemic structure of ideas as well as the psycho/ideological mechanisms responsible for them. In any case, philosophical systems are explicit conceptual structures, which, whatever motivates them, are, as systems and as products growing out of intellectual traditions and problems, constrained to develop into coherent logical configurations. Hence, while the categorical imperative (or idealism in general) may partake of the motivation of taboo, denial, amnesia, or repression, as a concept it can not be made any sense of in such terms. Adorno explains Kant in a way Freud cannot. Herein lies the essential limitation of a book conceived along these lines. ___________________ "People who believe absurdities commit atrocities."--Voltaire --- from list habermas-AT-lists.village.virginia.edu ---
Display software: ArchTracker © Malgosia Askanas, 2000-2005