Date: Wed, 27 Jan 1999 13:57:36 +0100 Subject: Re: Heidegger in Germany Cologne 27 January 1999 Thanks to Rene, Henk, Greg, Rafael, Antti for all the responses yesterday. I’ll try to reply to some of them. Henk: > In the case of Heidegger, I _just_ plead for a > critical attitude until we know where and how - > i.e. what to avoid. Avoid the illusion that philosophical thinking could find an immediate precipitation in political life. It seems that Heidegger realized this after lurching into the breech, later on in his Auseinandersetzung with Nietzsche (“Thoughts that come on pigeons’ feet steer the world.”) Marx, too, wanted to short-circuit philosophical thinking and politics, and that in a more deep-seated, programmatic way. His popularized theory was an historical disaster. I plea for a “critical attitude” altogether, not just because of political dangers. I plea for critical engagement (Auseinandersetzung) with the core of Heidegger’s thinking. How does _alaetheia_ reveal itself? Does Heidegger cover its full scope and reach? (Cf. my _Quivering of Propriation_, esp. the new Section 5, which I only put on site yesterday.) > Lotz tries to show that Husserl and Heidegger have more in > common than Heidegger allows for. He is one of those who > keep Heidegger alive - i.e. part of the philosophical > discours. I think Lotz is one of those who help put on the lid and shovel on a bit more dirt. The tone of his article is imbued with ownership rights, i.e. who thought what first, who is indebted to whom. It’s petty. Heidegger knew full well that he was deeply indebted to his teacher in phenomenology, and he also had his understanding of what separated him from Husserl. Whether this understanding was a misunderstanding is a secondary, academic question in my view. > For those who have devoted a lifetime to the study of his > thinking it must be painful to see how others treat it as > a thing: dissect it, quantify or qualify it, compare it, > etc. etc. Anyhow ... not taking it for what it pretends > to be - is. I don’t find it painful, just annoying and infuriating at times. As to pretence, it seems that many readers have their sport in trying to knock the thinker with his great insight down a peg or two. Call it inverted admiration, inferiority complex, the tall poppy syndrome or what you will. With this indignant attitude such a reader is not in the position to learn much from Heidegger. This does not disturb many academic readers. One can read a lot of books without thinking much at all. Antti: > I would agree with your interpretation of Heidegger - there's brilliant > stuff on this in GA 29, for example, where he patiently explains why he > believes propositional truth is secondary, and, incidentally, _argues_ for > it. The problem is that Habermas knows this too, and criticizes Heidegger > nonetheless. I'd say that the short version of his argument on the link > between Heidegger's philosophy and his Nazism is as follows: when you > believe that Truth-with-a-capital-T "takes place" in some "deeper" level of > "experience" than public discussion, you risk sliding towards taking the > originary "revelation" to the chosen ones, Thinkers-with-a-capital-T, as > something that does not have to be justified before and to the Other: "All > refutation in the field of essential thinking is foolish." (Letter on > Humanism, p. 239 in _Basic Writings_). Belief in the inner truth and > greatness of your own thinking, your own German nation, regardless of what > others think or say is what makes possible silencing, or gassing, the > others, the parasites. I do not see any necessary link between regarding oneself as great and wanting others to be silenced. That is a merely suggestive concatenation. As for wanting others to be murdered, a few more monstrous links would be necessary. Greatness can go only with humility. Rafael has already replied to you with some insightful remarks, including the one that it is a mistake to think of _alaetheia_ as truth with a capital T or otherwise. _alaetheia_ is the opening for the play of disclosure _and_ covering up. It is where truth can take place, not truth itself. We are beings exposed to seeing and failing to see, to lucid views and distorted ones. It is not as if the insight into _alaetheia_ were the guarantee for privately possessing _a_ truth. Nor does the step back from propositional truth into the clearing mean that one has moved simply to a zone of experience that cannot be brought to language. Phenomenology means, after all, putting the phenomena into words, and that implies that phenomenological truth is necessarily shared. (But it is shared even before words!) If, like Habermas, one wants to insist on rational argument (no matter how this rationality is conceived) to the exclusion of what cannot be put into words, this amounts to truncating what human being is and can be by pushing out of sight what is out of proportion with this _ratio_. It must then bear the ominous title, the Irrational, as something to be feared and kept under control by rationality. That is Habermas’ tack against thinkers like Heidegger and Nietzsche, who for him are Irrationalists. Heidegger is for Habermas a thinker who “undermines occidental rationalism” (cf. the title of the Heidegger chapter in _Der philosophische Diskurs der Moderne_). The alternative is to enter into the full openness of what human being means in its full exposure to beyng and try to point to the phenomena associated with this ‘being human’. Our bodiliness, for instance, will never be amenable to propositional truth but requires another sensibility and perceptiveness if we are to escape the natural-scientific understanding of our body. We don’t just share the truth of statements but the reverberation of atmospheres, say, of excitement. What shows itself in the moodedness of existence? Does it _show_ itself? One way of understanding the quote: "All refutation in the field of essential thinking is foolish." is that all the great thinkers are guided by an insight which serves as fountain-head for their respective philosophies. This insight has always been (in the history of metaphysics) a casting of the being of beings. To move beyond a thinker, one first has to try to catch a glimpse oneself of this guiding insight, i.e. to _learn_ from that thinker. Refutation is an inadequate concept for understanding the relationship of Aristotle to Plato, Leibniz to Descartes, Hegel to Kant, Marx to Hegel, Heidegger to Husserl, etc. By chance I have also found the passage in Habermas where you quote him quoting Heidegger’s "All refutation...”. The very next sentence after that (in the “Letter on Humanism”, Heidegger writes: “The dispute between thinkers is the ‘loving dispute’ about the issue itself.” (_Wegmarken_ S.333) Whereas “refutation” can be conceived in rational terms, a “loving dispute” bursts this rationalistic framework and brings in the passion of philosophy and the exposure to the thinker’s task of a total casting of the world. > For Habermas, truth can never be anybody's private property. Having said > that, I don't mean to imply that Heidegger would think otherwise; In GA27 you will find sections where Heidegger shows why the clearing of truth is necessarily shared. Mitsein means, first and foremost, sharing the clearing. > Heidegger > is not a philosopher of will-to-power, on the contrary, and _aletheia_ is > not subjective. This, I grant, Habermas might well have missed. But it > would be foolish to deny that Heidegger has a tendency to use a dangerous > rhetoric of privileged access, from beginning to end. The very idea of a > depth beyond the reach of ordinary people and public discourse is what > metaphysics is all about. I don’t see it as “privileged access” at all because there is nobody handing out privileges here. Certainly it is a matter of the “rare few”, for access to philosophical thinking is difficult and involves giving back (putting on hold) all the ways of thinking which one takes for granted. But in principle it is open to anyone. Philosophy is one of the few human endeavours which cuts across social class. Nietzsche wrote for “Everybody and Nobody”, i.e. the door is open, but few enter. And there are diverse potentials for cross-fertilizations between philosophers and people involved in other endeavours. Heidegger’s talk of the “rare few” in the _Beitraege zur Philosophie_ (GA65) seems to me to be born (at least in part) of the bitter realization that a fundamental shift within the history of Western thinking cannot connect with any mass movement or even a reform of the German universities. He could also see by that time just how thoroughly _Sein und Zeit_ was being misunderstood. And he was very inept in politics. > propositional conceptions of truth are metaphysical. And Habermas is > one of the very few philosophers who have actually argued why truth should > be conceived as property of statements rather than experience (see his > 'Wahrheitstheorien' in _Vorstudien und Ergänzungen zur Theorie des > kommunikativen Handelns_, Suhrkamp 1984). Thanks for the reference. > What I would like to see is an account of truth that gives absolute > privilege neither to discourse or to disclosure. I don’t know what “absolute privilege” is with respect to _alaetheia_ (which should not be equated with disclosure). Isn’t it just a matter of gaining an insight into what is meant by the “clearing”? And with this insight, other phenomena too could become clearer (for instance, the Other) and thought through more adequately. > I thought the innermost heart of the thinking of being could not be brought > to argumentative language.... Seriously, it will always be possible to for > you to say that someone hasn't understood "the innermost heart of the > thinking of being"; you can not be refuted by any number of passages, and > that is precisely the problem. Having quickly looked over the Heidegger chapter in Habermas’ _Der philosophische Diskurs der Moderne_ once again, I think I can see where you are coming from with your remarks. I think Habermas is appallingly bad on Heidegger, but I do not expect anybody to take me at my word. There would be a lot to say in an adequate critique of Habermas’ Heidegger critique. Here just a couple of points. 1) Habermas is keen on nailing Heidegger to a fixation on his teacher, Husserl. Habermas wants to show that Heidegger thus remains tied negatively tied to Husserl and what Habermas calls “Subjektphilosophie”. Habermas does not realize just how much Heidegger owes to Aristotle and Plato. It is the interpretation (the phenomenological reading) of these fathers of metaphysics which allows Heidegger to unearth what _alaetheuein_ means. Habermas does not venture to comment on Heidegger’s reading of Pl. and Arist., presumably because he is out of his depth in the beginnings of metaphysics. 2) Habermas therefore reads the Zeuganalyse in SuZ as a kind of pragmatism which does not offer anything beyond the “pragmatism from Peirce to Mead and Dewey” (Habermas S.176) He can only do this because he fails to see that Heidegger’s aim in analyzing equipment is to show that handling equipment in everyday life is a mode of _alaetheuein_! This becomes especially clear if one reads e.g. GA19 _Sophistes_. For Habermas, Heidegger overcomes “Bewusstseinsphilosophie”, but so does pragmatism, so Heidegger is merely on a par with Peirce, Mead and Dewey. 3) Habermas represents SuZ as the result of several “begriffsstrategischen Entscheidungen” (decisions relating to conceptual strategy; S.174). This is antithetical to Heidegger’s phenomenological approach in which it is a matter of pointing to (in language, with the _logos_) the phenomena as they show themselves of themselves. Habermas refuses to acknowledge that Heidegger’s analysis of das Man is not motivated by cultural critique (as Heidegger explicitly points out), but insists it is part of a “conceptual strategy” to include “existenzphilosophische Motive” (S.174) which could “at the same time serve as an answer to the practical question as to how to live correctly” (S.175) It does not seem to have any effect that the text _SuZ_, and also later texts, explicitly attempt to rule out this existentialist misunderstanding and point in another direction. Rather, das Man has to be understood, if at all, as a happening of _alaetheia_ too, namely, as a covering-over. Only on this basis can this phenomenological analysis be criticized, not by violently attributing “strategic conceptual decisions” to its author and treating him as just another “German mandarin” (S.167). 4) Because Habermas has no insight into _alaetheia_, he cannot conceive of the world as a space where the play of _alaetheia_ happens and where Dasein is only the playmate of _alaetheia_, not an originator of theoretical models. He thinks the life-world as “being suspended, so to speak, in the structures of linguistic intersubjectivity” (S.177) and laments that Heidegger did not pass down the path of “such an answer in terms of communication theory”. But this shows that Habermas himself remains tied to the metaphysics of subjectivity, namely, that of intersubjectivity. The world can only be thought as something between the subjects, not as a being-in-the-world for which the play of the world itself is primary. 5) Because Habermas has no insight into _alaetheia_, he also cannot follow Heidegger’s thinking beyond _SuZ_. In reading SuZ, Habermas can at least understand Dasein as a sort-of subject. Once Heidegger dispenses with the preludium of a Daseinsanalytik, he becomes totally incomprehensible to Habermas. Heidegger becomes then a mere master in rhetoric. For instance: “Because being eludes assertative grasping by descriptive sentences, because it can only be circled and ‘ensilenced’ in indirect speech, the destinies of being remain unfathomable. The propositionally substanceless talk of being has nevertheless the illocutionary sense of demanding submission to destiny. Its practical-political side consists in the perlocutionary effect of a willingness to obey an auratic but indeterminate authority whose content is diffuse. The rhetoric of the late Heidegger...” (S.168) Then come the skilfully arrayed quotes about the “shepherd of being”, etc. So the late Heidegger is for Habermas a preacher of blind submission to destiny. Habermas gets nervous at the idea that there could be something happening which is not in the hands of subjects. He insists on language games as the (rational) limits of playfulness. He insists on disclosure and does not want to acknowledge that there could be something like a play of disclosure _and_ covering-over. But already in SuZ, Dasein is exposed to the play of revealing and concealing in the Da; it just does not look as threatening in an analysis of everyday life. Habermas hangs onto and is “suspended in the structures of linguistic intersubjectivity” for dear life. That’s enough for now. Plato says roughly: _Oudeis hekon hamartanei_ (cf. Rep. 589c) "Nobody misses the point willingly." Michael _-_-_-_-_-_-_-_-_-_- artefact text and translation _-_-_-_-_-_-_-_-_-_- _-_-_-_-_-_-_-_-_-_-_-_-_-_-_- made by art _-_-_-_-_-_-_-_-_-_-_-_-_-_- http://www.webcom.com/artefact/ _-_-_-_-_-_-_-_ artefact-AT-t-online.de-_-_ _-_-_-_-_-_-_-_-_-_-_-_-_-_-_-_-_-_-_-_-_-_-_-_ Dr Michael Eldred -_-_-_ _-_-_-_-_-_-_-_-_-_-_-_-_-_-_-_-_-_-_-_-_-_-_-_-_-_-_-_-_-_-_-_-_-_-_-_- --- from list heidegger-AT-lists.village.virginia.edu ---
Display software: ArchTracker © Malgosia Askanas, 2000-2005