Subject: Re: Being and Time - Div I, Ch 1 questions Date: Fri, 22 Jan 1999 11:41:53 -0600 (CST) <aglynn-AT-idirect.com> wrote: > Ryan Stubblefield <vorpal-AT-iname.com> said: > >The first paragraph is in Section 9, second full paragraph of p. 44 in > >the German. It begins with "But the explication of Dasein in its average > >everydaynes..." and ends "...certain ontological characteristics of an > >authentic Being of Dasein. > > I think this points forward in the book towards the ability to 'get' > Dasein in one's grasp ontologically as-a-whole, and to ascertain > characteristics of a potential authentic Dasein distinct from Dasein in > its everyday averageness, despite everyday averageness being the starting > point of the analysis. I agree. Everydayness is averageness because in it there is no significant difference between particular existing Da-seins. As a way of existing that particular Da-seins all have in common, the differences between this Da-sein and that Da-sein in everydayness are differences that make no difference. But while particular Da-seins are indeterminate in this way with respect to their common everydayness, it does not follow that everydayness as a way of existing is itself indeterminate. Everydayness is ontically average (and to that extent indeterminate) because the differences between particular everyday Da-seins are ontical differences. But everydayness is not ontologically average, because it is one of two determinate ways in which the existing of Da-sein can show itself, and the inferior one to boot. These two ways of existing, inauthenticity and authenticity, are the two ways in which the Being of Da-sein is actualizable. They are the two ways in which Da-sein can relate itself to its Being, and therewith to Being as such. The analysis of everydayness is the analysis of inauthenticity, but the aim of the analysis is to get hold of the common structure of inauthenticity and authenticity, i.e. the relating to (its) Being. Perhaps this paragraph (and _BT_ as a whole) would be a little clearer if, every time you see "inauthentic" or "authentic," you read it as "improper" or "proper." This would be a somewhat more literal translation of the German, one that ties in to Heidegger's remark in Section 7 (p. 38 in the German) that the transcendence of the Being of Da-sein enfolds the potential for individuation. To be authentic (proper) is to individuate oneself, so that one's existing is proper to oneself. In authenticity the difference between oneself and another Da-sein is one that makes a difference, since what is proper to oneself as an individual need not be proper to another. There will still be a commonality of ontological structure between particular Da-seins that exist properly, but this commonality is not, in Heidegger's view, a matter of averageness. > >The second is the first full paragraph of p. 46 in the German, beginning > >"At the same time it is of course misleading..." and ending "...in > >designation those entities which we are ourselves" > > Heidegger is pointing out that he is not simply analysing the historiology > of philosophy but jumping away from it by using the term Dasein, > "Existence", a neutral term that allows Heidegger to both bring the > entities which we are ourselves in a relation to Being (Being/Existence), > and avoid any claims that Dasein is an actual thingly present-at-hand > extant object. It's true that Heidegger is analyzing the history of philosophy in a critical way, and to that extent distancing himself from the presuppositions of philosophy he discovers in the analysis. I think it's wrong, though, or at best misleading, to say that "Da-sein" is a neutral term, if only because Heidegger is not simply avoiding the claim that the beings designated by "Da-sein" are objectively present beings (Stambaugh's translation of _Vorhandenen_) but actively denying it. "Da-sein" has a double sense that is not neutral but rather is based in Heidegger's fundamental presuppositions concerning Being, namely phenomenality and the ontological difference. On the one hand, "Da-sein" means "existence," and therefore expresses the distinctive Being of the beings we ourselves are. "Existence" can't be meant neutrally here, because for Heidegger existing, relating oneself in one's Being to one's Being, can only be phenomenal. It's true that Heidegger takes over the term from the tradition in which he found himself, but it's just as true that the term doesn't have the same meaning when he uses it as it does in the tradition. On the other hand, "Da-sein" means "there-Being." It expresses, not the Being of the being that exists, but Being as such. That is, it expresses the whole of possibilities of beings as a whole wherein Da-sein exists and to which it relates itself in existing. In a word, "Da-sein" as there-Being designates the world (in the sense in which the later Heidegger uses this word, not the sense in _BT_, which applies only to beings whose Being is not existence). To the extent that there is existing (and therewith handiness [Stambaugh's translation of _Zuhandenheit_) and objective presence], there is also and necessarily the world wherein existing occurs, the way in which existing and handiness and objective presence are gathered together into a whole. The difference between existing and the world is the ontological difference. Heidegger calls the beings we ourselves are "Da-sein" not only because we are the beings that exist, but also (and perhaps primarily) because we are the place where the ontological difference can show itself. Later... -- Ronald M. Carrier -- rcarrier-AT-{suba.com,hecky.acns.nwu.edu} http://www.suba.com/~rcarrier/ "If one does nothing but listen to the new music, everything else drifts, goes away, frays."--Donald Barthelme --- from list heidegger-AT-lists.village.virginia.edu ---
Display software: ArchTracker © Malgosia Askanas, 2000-2005