Date: Mon, 12 Mar 2001 20:14:08 -0600 Subject: Re: Terror & the Sublime Julie, Hugh et al., First some pedantic comments relative to Kant. There seems to be some conflation here between beauty and the sublime. As I read Kant, they remain two very distinct moments of the aesthetic judgement. Beauty gives us disinterested pleasure based on a reflective judgement without a concept, that judges "x is beautiful". As such, it is a universal statement of taste concerning a particular object. Anyone, without bias, should make the same judgement, upon encountering that x. The sublime is a very different kind of aesthetic judgement. While the beautiful concerns the form of the object, the sublime can also be found in a formless object. It is characterized by a certain boundlessness. Kant distinguishes two kinds of sublime - mathematical and dynamic. The former is concerned with infinity; the second with power and might. (It is only in the second that terror plays a role. Hence, terror is not a necessary component of the sublime.) Kant completely rejects the empiricism of Burke. For him, the sublime is not found in nature per se, but rather in the conflict of the faculties. At first this conflict is experienced as painful since the imagination strives in vain to present itself with an Idea of reason. Ultimately, this is transformed into sublime pleasure because reason comes to realize itself as a supersensible power standing above nature and beyond the productive imagination as well. I believe the key move that Lyotard makes regarding the sublime is to remove it from the Kantian faculties and situate it into a heterogeneous and incommeasurable phrase universe - from the subject to language. This move has several aspects. Julie referred to the figure as being sublime, but the figure retains a certain form, even though it resists absorption into discourse. Jeremy Gibert-Rolfe has made the following comments that bear on this. "Beauty, on the other hand, is surely nothing of the sort. Along with Lyotard, Michael Fried and Steven Bann have also pursued the distinction- also eighteenth century in origin - between an art in which one looks at something and an art which would be about that act of looking, an art in which one would look at oneself looking...Beauty, in contradistinction , would have to be visible from the first. It was never other than visible, never needed to be brought into view. Except, of course, when it had been suppressed. In this formulation, beauty would be that which cannot be reduced to its critique, to the sublime that is realized in critique and in the object of self-consciousness, in the self that finds itself in wondering about what it means to be or have a self." "it's that beauty is not critical nor a product of criticism, and, as such, can only undermine that regime of good sense that is criticism's search for meaning. Beauty, in being frivolous, and in that trivial and irrelevant, is always subversive because it's always a distraction from the worthwhile, which let's us know it's worthwhile by not being beautiful." What I find remarkable about this passage is that in the guise of critiquing Lyotard, Gilbert-Rolfe appears to be describing the same kind of ambiguous relationship that Lyotard himself made between discourse and figure, although Lyotard does not necessarily privilege the figural as beauty. As far as the sublime is concerned, both the incredulity towards metanarratives and the feeling of incommeasurability brought about by the differend are unbounded signs that the sublime is being felt. Here, however, it is not found in the play of the faculties, but it the heterogeneous phrases themselves. These must be linked, but no rule or genre allows them to be linked necessarily. Thus, there is a referral back to the reflective judgement which experiences this incommeasurability itself as an alteration of pain and pleasure, filled with libidinal intensities. This feeling is sublime, but different in many respects from the way it was previously situated by both Burke and Kant. I agree the art can paradoxically "present" this unpresentable sublime and even what is commonly referred to as "postmodern art" attempts to do this, somewhat intentionally, by mixing genres and being self-reflexive. However, much of the value of Lyotard's reworking of the sublime points as well in the rudderless direction of ethics and politics. (Which is not to say that there is a politics of the sublime.) Art is related to politics because both are concerned with the articulation of affects, although the consequences of this may differ greatly. 1
Display software: ArchTracker © Malgosia Askanas, 2000-2005