Date: Thu, 5 Sep 1996 12:50:55 -0600 (MDT) Subject: *Marx, Hayek, and Utopia* Now, i am finally in a position to pursue an analysis and discussion of Chris Sciabarra's book *Marx, Hayek, and Utopia* SUNY Press: Albany, 1995 (here after MHU). My primary interest in MHU is twofold: (a) Sciabarria's interest in dialectics (as a method of [social] reasoning); and (b) his attempt to find commonalities between these (ontologically) oppossed traditions. i will go through the book chapter by chapter (for the most part), in numerical order. MHU has an intoduciton, 7 chapters, and an epilogue. One main thesis of MHU is that the "traditional" interpretations of the opposing tradition tend to underestimate, misunderstand, and misrepresent one another. First, the Hayek camp tending to dismiss Marxists as utopian; and second Marxians reducing Hayekians to capitalist apologists. Both which Sciabarra wants to challenge as misled. Or as Sciabarra himself puts it on the frist page of MHU: "Each side has expressed the conviction that the other is dismally wrong. However, it is my belief that each has a great deal to learn from the other: Hayekians, who dismiss Marx as a utopian, might detect a significant anti-utopian dimension in his thought; Marxists, who dismiss Hayek as an apologist for capitalism, might discover a certain dialectical sensibility in his thought." One great commonality between Marx and Hayek is their shared commitment to anti-utopian thought. This will turn up again and again throughtout the pages of MHU. Sciabarra adds: "And yet, despite their common anti-utopianism, Marx and Hayek differ with regard to some crucially important epistemic premises" (Sciabarra:2). These "epistemic premises" will be shown to be in latter chapters (1) the "unintended consequences" of individual *action* and (especially) intentional political or collective policy; and (2) unacknowledged conditions of such 'action' and 'policy'. Together constituting the limits of human cognitive reasoning and understanding; and hence questioning the ability of human beings to make social change for the betterment of the human condition. This last sentence pushes Sciabarra's own words, but it is a theme that the reader (at least this one) is left with throughout the book. A type of (liberal) Skepticism (if you will). One that must be addressed by radical social thinkers. And if held, a position that must be defended by the liberal social thinkers. It is worth continuing with the last quote in full, which is as follows: "For Hayek, Marx's vision of the ideal communist society rests on the mistaken assumption that in the future, people will be capable of mastering their own destiny. In Hayek's view, this grandiose Marxist illusion served as an ideological legitimation for modern attempts to achieve the millennium through the coercive power of the state. Hayek explains that for important ontological and epistemological reasons, such a utopian goal must engender dystopian consequences. For Marxists, however, any such epistemic constraints are historically specific to capitalism. Such critics as Hilary Wainwright contend that Hayek embarces a 'dogmatically individualist' view of knowledge that does not recognize the potential for efficacious collective action" (ibid). i would like to point out a few things that are revealed in this quote. The main thing being the political tone of reasoning that is embedded in Sciabarra's work. That is to say he has a very political presentation of Hayek and Marx. Sciabarra uses this political presentation especially against Marxists, often (i hope to demonstrate) missing the explanatory strength of a Marxian understanding of capitalism as a socio-economic system. But this is not to deny the weaknesses of the dogmatic Marxists committed to the "whithering" away of misery and misfortune with the absenting of capitalist social realtions. Or to put in different, more critical, words: a weakness of Sciabarra's book is its lack of economic reasoning. An absence that seems to put his interpretation of Marx at a disadvantage of his interpretation of Hayek. In other words, i do not believe necessarily that Marx's view (and faith & hope) of the future social possibilities is directly connected with his understanding of the dynamics or social dialectic of the capitalist system. Whether we can "master" our own "destiny" does not necessarily commit us to capitalism or socialism -- if we can disspell Marxists from this "grandiose" "illusion" we are not necessarily committing ourselves to the "free market". This is the theme of Wainwright's book. Connceted to these "epistemic differences" is a particular ontological commitment to what constitutes human beings themselves and the societies they create. In this respect, i will defend Wainwright against Sciabarra's criticism later in the book. But for now i will quickly finish the Introduction. Sciabarra offers a history of "dialectic", which is much too brief. His comments and footnote on Aristole are the most interesting. Sciabarra claims that: "The best way in which to understand the dialectical impulse is to view it as a *method* of social inquiry" (Sciabarra:4). i am not at all sure about this statement. i do not necessarily believe we should reduce diaelctics to merely to a "method". Dialectics is an *implicit* ontological commitment, one which dialectical and transcendental reasoning attempts to make *explicit*. But in any event Sciabarra maintains dialectic is a method which in part determines the content, or there exists a reciprocity of "the 'how' and the 'what' -- of one's analysis". i agree with this, but will attempt to push Chris on his meaning of dialectics throughout my reading of MHU. i did very much like it when Sciabarra says: "The dialectical method recognizes that what is separable in thought is not separable in reality" (Sciabarra:4). This is related to my comments about dialectics and ontology; and suggests that we must be on guard against (what Bhaskar calls) categorical errors. Or our tendency to apply our categories erroneously to reality; consequently mis-understanding reality itself, hence our ability to change it. There is also a nice statement of dialectic in the last paragraph of page four and first paragraph of page five (which i will not reproduce here). This is the best pronoucement of dialectics in the book. Although the entire book is developing a notion of dialectic, if only implicitly. i will stop here, but to anticipate, i am very suspicious of what is meant by dialectics in this book. And will attempt to point out the when a more economic type of reasoning could benefit. hans d. --- from list marxism2-AT-lists.village.virginia.edu ---
Display software: ArchTracker © Malgosia Askanas, 2000-2005