Date: Thu, 12 Sep 1996 23:41:37 -0600 (MDT) Subject: Re: *Marx, Hayek, and Utopia Below is a review of chapter one of Sciabarra's *Marx, Hayek, and Utopia* (1995). i will continue to develop this chapter to chapter, but there needs to be a overall assetment to discuss the major issues. Chapter one of MHU is titled "Hayekian Dialectics". The first section of this chapter attempts to define Hayek's political and social positions or views. Sciabarra claims Hayek is not (necessarily) conserative, nor reactionary, and certainly not an apologist for the capitalist system. In brief Sciabarra argues Hayek is: (1) a classical liberal toward the ("free") market; (2) conservative toward evolutionism (as opposed to violent revolution); and (3) "profoundly radical" in his commitment to a dialectical method of social theory (Sciabarra:12). There is not much textual support offered for these claims (there are references); but i would tend to agree this interpretation is easily supported by Hayek himself. The main trouble being (3), namely the title of the chapter itself -- in what way can we say Hayek is dialectical? This will be especially important in that Sciabarra's argument throughout MHU is there exists two main inflection points in the work of Marx and Hayek, which offers a certain common ground for communicability between the two camps. These inflection points are (a) dialectical method; and (b) anti-utopian commitments. Where (a) is usually (or dogmatically) understood to be strictly Marxian; and (b) is held to be strictly characteristic of evolutionalism. Sciabarra attempts to demonstrate (a) and (b) charactrize both camps, and hence offers a unique and important possiblity for a commonality that exists between the Hayekian and Marxian traditions where there is most often understood to be none. Sciabarra's case is well made for (a) and (b) charactrizing both Hayek and Marx (it is interesting how cherished utopianism is on this list as a Marxian commitment). However, personally i have reservations with the case made for (a) and will attempt to critique this aspect of MHU in posts to come. In any event, Sciabarra's purpose in the first section of chapter one seems to be to argue for the strenghs of the Hayekian commitments (1-3 above). For example, one argument is that a commitment to evolution is not necessarily a commitment to the status quo. Rather the importance of history, the timing, and rate of change are of the utmost importance for being effective and successful in social transformation. BTW i take this to be the central (implicit) theme in Karl Polanyi's *The Great Transformation*. K. Polanyi's is usually understood as a radical (though not usually Marxian). The next section is a defense against the strict methodological individualist interpretations of Hayek. Admittly, i am not familiar enough with Hayek to agree or critique the accuracy of such an interpretation. However, i have developed enough "faith" in the author to accept this is an imporvished reading of Hayek (in whole). However, Sciabarra's wants to critique Hilary Wainwright for mis-(or under-)interpreting Hayek as a "dogmatic individualist". He insists that the "framework" of Hayek "relects a deep appreciation for organic social interrelationships and their dynamic development over time" (Sciabarra:15); and not a dogmatic individualist. There may be truth to this, but i will (passively) suggest there is not necessarily anything mistaken with saying there is a general tendency in some (or much) of Hayek's work to interpret him as a dogmatic individualist. Moreover, Wainwright's own interest is in understanding the appeal of the free-market right. i have read Wainwright's book, but my interest did not have these issues in mind at the time, hence, this is all i am able to say. But i am curious if her comments on Hayek as a "dogmatic individualist" are political or methodological. i would suggest that politically a defender of the "free-market" would tend to be an individualist; while the Austrians in general are methodologically individualists. But according to Sciabarra Hayek does not necessarily commitment himself to a reductionist, atomistic methodology of social analysis: "while Hayek recognizes the ontological priority of concrete particulars, of real, existing individuals, he views the whole as a relationally evolving totality that is beyond the capacity of any single individual to fully comprehend" (Sciabarra:17-8). And in the next section Hayek is quoted as saying: "social theory must start 'from men whose nature and character is detemined by their existence in society'" (Sciabarra quoting Hayek:25). Hayek is in agreement with M. Polanyi (Karl Polanyi's bother) when the latter "argues that 'all particulars become meaningless if we lose sight of the pattern which they jointly constitute'" (19). In all Sciabarra is quite convincing in making a case for Hayek being methodologically *relational* but does this make him necessarily *dialectical*. i would like to come back to this issue further along in the book itself, but will state dialectics is a commitment to a particular ontological view. Dialectics is not merely a "method" (Sciabarra:4) or "a way of thinking" (Sciabarra:24). It is uncovering, or making explicit this ontology that in part makes a thinker dialectic, and it is here that we must question the commonality between Marx and Hayek (and Hegel for that matter). The next section of the chapter does begin to develop a more specific and explicit ontology by discussing "internal relations". In short, this section of the book is very well done. But i may suggest that it belongs in the introduction as part of the defination of dialectics itself. With an apology i will not develop or attempt to reproduce Sciabarra's presentation of "internal relations". Rather (unfairly?!) i will focus on a disagreement. Sciabarra (page 25) says: "For Hayek, there is a limit beyond which we are unable to articulate the rules, customs, and habits that govern our lives. We are *internal* to these rules and cannot take an external, transcendental role. Even our consciousness operates according to rules of which we are not conscious, since these rules are *internal* to the operation itself." The first sentence suggests there is an ontological limit for human beings, but is this really the case? There are certainly difficulties, and epistemological problems, but i am not at all sure this should commitment to a general limit for all human beings, and to the production of knowledge a priori. Second it is the transcendental role (at least in the Kantian usage of the term) that offers us hope in re-constructing reality in thought. That is we can always ask the transcendental type of question -- what must (social) reality itself be like for our experience to be as it is? Once we understand social reality, we can change it in an attempt to absence particular unwanted manifestations. We do not necessarily need to know all of reality to change part of it for the better. Moreover, this should not in itself commitment to any particular social system. This is a theme of Wainwright's book which i think is very important. Namely there is hope in transforming reality for the betterment of the human condition. i will end here. hans despain --- from list marxism2-AT-lists.village.virginia.edu ---
Display software: ArchTracker © Malgosia Askanas, 2000-2005